Structuralism
is appealing to some critics because it adds a certain objectivity, a
SCIENTIFIC objectivity, to the realm of literary studies (which have often been
criticized as purely subjective/impressionistic). This scientific objectivity
is achieved by subordinating “parole” to “langue;” actual usage is abandoned in
favor of studying the structure of a system in the abstract. Thus structuralist
readings ignore the specificity of actual texts and treat them as if they were
like the patterns produced by iron filings moved by magnetic force–the result
of some impersonal force or power, not the result of human effort.
In
structuralism, the individuality of the text disappears in favor of looking at
patterns, systems, and structures. Some structuralists (and a related school of
critics, called the Russian Formalists) propose that ALL narratives can be
charted as variations on certain basic universal narrative patterns.
In
this way of looking at narratives, the author is canceled out, since the text
is a function of a system, not of an individual. The Romantic humanist model
holds that the author is the origin of the text, its creator, and hence is the
starting point or progenitor of the text. Structuralism argues that any piece
of writing, or any signifying system, has no origin, and that authors merely
inhabit pre-existing structures (langue) that enable them to make any
particular sentence (or story)–any parole. Hence the idea that “language speaks
us,” rather than that we speak language. We don’t originate language; we
inhabit a structure that enables us to speak; what we (mis)perceive as our
originality is simply our recombination of some of the elements in the
pre-existing system. Hence every text, and every sentence we speak or write, is
made up of the “already written.”
By
focusing on the system itself, in a synchronic analysis, structuralists cancel
out history. Most insist, as Levi-Strauss does, that structures are universal,
therefore timeless. Structuralists can’t account for change or development;
they are uninterested, for example, in how literary forms may have changed over
time. They are not interested in a text’s production or reception/consumption,
but only in the structures that shape it.
In
erasing the author, the individual text, the reader, and history, structuralism
represented a major challenge to what we now call the “liberal humanist”
tradition in literary criticism.
The
HUMANIST model presupposed:
1.)
That there is a real world out there that we can understand with our rational
minds.
2.)
That language is capable of (more or less) accurately depicting that real
world..
3.)
That language is a product of the individual writer’s mind or free will,
meaning that we determine what we say, and what we mean when we say it; that
language thus expresses the essence of our individual beings (and that there is
such a thing as an essential unique individual “self”).
4.)
the SELF–also known as the “subject,” since that’s how we represent the idea of
a self in language, by saying I, which is the subject of a sentence–or the
individual (or the mind or the free will) is the center of all meaning and
truth; words mean what I say they mean, and truth is what I perceive as truth.
I create my own sentences out of my own individual experiences and need for
individual expression.
The
STRUCTURALIST model argues
1.)
that the structure of language itself produces “reality”–that we can think only
through language, and therefore our perceptions of reality are all framed by
and determined by the structure of language.
2.)
That language speaks us; that the source of meaning is not an individual’s
experience or being, but the sets of oppositions and operations, the signs and
grammars that govern language. Meaning doesn’t come from individuals, but from
the system that governs what any individual can do within it.
3.)
Rather than seeing the individual as the center of meaning, structuralism
places THE STRUCTURE at the center–it’s the structure that originates or
produces meaning, not the individual self. Language in particular is the center
of self and meaning; I can only say “I” because I inhabit a system of language
in which the position of subject is marked by the first personal pronoun, hence
my identity is the product of the linguistic system I occupy.
This
is also where deconstruction starts to come in. The leading figure in
deconstruction, Jacques Derrida, looks at philosophy (Western metaphysics) to
see that any system necessarily posits a CENTER, a point from which everything
comes, and to which everything refers or returns. Sometimes it’s God, sometimes
it’s the human self, the mind, sometimes it’s the unconscious, depending on
what philosophical system (or set of beliefs) one is talking about.
There
are two key points to the idea of deconstruction. First is that we’re still
going to look at systems or structures, rather than at individual concrete
practices, and that all systems or structures have a CENTER, the point of
origin, the thing that created the system in the first place. Second is that
all systems or structures are created of binary pairs or oppositions, of two
terms placed in some sort of relation to each.
Derrida
says that such systems are always built of the basic units structuralism
analyzes–the binary opposition or pair–and that within these systems one part
of that binary pair is always more important than the other, that one term is
“marked” as positive and the other as negative. Hence in the binary pair
good/evil, good is what Western philosophy values, and evil is subordinated to
good. Derrida argues that all binary pairs work this way–light/dark,
masculine/feminine, right/left; in Western culture, the first term is always
valued over the second.
In
his most famous work, Of Grammatology, Derrida looks particularly at the
opposition speech/writing, saying that speech is always seen as more important
than writing. This may not be as self-evident as the example of good/evil, but
it’s true in terms of linguistic theories, where speech is posited as the first
or primary form of language, and writing is just the transcription of speech.
Derrida says speech gets privileged because speech is associated with
presence–for there to be spoken language, somebody has to be there to be
speaking.
No,
he doesn’t take into account tape recordings and things like that. Remember, a
lot of what these guys are talking about has roots in philosophic and
linguistic traditions that predate modern technology–so that Derrida is
responding to an opposition (speech/writing) that Plato set up, long before
there were tape recorders. Just like poor old Levi-Strauss talks about how, in
order to map all the dimensions of a myth, he’d have to have “punch cards and
an IBM machine,” when all he’d need now is a home computer.
Anyway,
the idea is that the spoken word guarantees the existence of somebody doing the
speaking–thus it reinforces all those great humanist ideas, like that there’s a
real self that is the origin of what’s being said. Derrida calls this idea of
the self that has to be there to speak part of the metaphysics of PRESENCE; the
idea of being, or presence, is central to all systems of Western philosophy,
from Plato through Descartes (up to Derrida himself). Presence is part of a
binary opposition presence/absence, in which presence is always favored over
absence. Speech gets associated with presence, and both are favored over
writing and absence; this privileging of speech and presence is what Derrida
calls LOGOCENTRISM.
You
might think here about the Biblical phrase “Let there be light” as an example.
The statement insures that there is a God (the thing doing the speaking), and
that God is present (because speech=presence); the present God is the origin of
all things (because God creates the world by speaking), and what God creates is
binary oppositions (starting with light/dark). You might also think about other
binary oppositions or pairs, including being/nothingness, reason/madness,
word/silence, culture/nature, mind/body. Each term has meaning only in
reference to the other (light is what is not dark, and vice-versa), just as, in
Saussure’s view, signifiers only have meaning–or negative value–in relation to
other signifiers. These binary pairs are the “structures,” or fundamental opposing
ideas, that Derrida is concerned with in Western philosophy.
Because
of the favoring of presence over absence, speech is favored over writing (and,
as we’ll see with Freud, masculine is favored over feminine because the penis
is defined as a presence, whereas the female genitals are defined as absence).
It’s
because of this favoring of presence over absence that every system (I’m
referring here mostly to philosophical systems, but the idea works for
signifying systems as well) posits a CENTER, a place from which the whole
system comes, and which guarantees its meaning–this center guarantees being as
presence. Think of your entire self as a kind of system–everything you do,
think, feel, etc. is part of that system. At the core or center of your mental and
physical life is a notion of SELF, of an “I”, of an identity that is stable and
unified and coherent, the part of you that knows who you mean when you say “I”.
This core self or “I” is thus the CENTER of the “system”, the “langue” of your
being, and every other part of you (each individual act) is part of the
“parole”. The “I” is the origin of all you say and do, and it guarantees the
idea of your presence, your being.
Western
thought has a whole bunch of terms that serve as centers to systems –being, essence,
substance, truth, form, consciousness, man, god, etc. What Derrida tells us is
that each of these terms designating the center of a system serves two
purposes: it’s the thing that created the system, that originated it and
guarantees that all the parts of the system interrelate, and it’s also
something beyond the system, not governed by the rules of the system. This is
what he talks about as a “scandal” discovered by Levi-Strauss in Levi-Strauss’s
thoughts about kinship systems. (This will be covered in detail in the next
lecture).
What
Derrida does is to look at how a binary opposition–the fundamental unit of the
structures or systems we’ve been looking at, and of the philosophical systems
he refers to–functions within a system. He points out that a binary opposition
is algebraic (a=~b, a equals not-b), and that two terms can’t exist without
reference to the other–light (as presence) is defined as the absence of
darkness, goodness the absence of evil, etc. He doesn’t seek to reverse the
hierarchies implied in binary pairs–to make evil favored over good, unconscious
over consciousness, feminine over masculine. Rather, deconstruction wants to
erase the boundaries (the slash) between oppositions, hence to show that the
values and order implied by the opposition are also not rigid.
Here’s
the basic method of deconstruction: find a binary opposition. Show how each
term, rather than being polar opposite of its paired term, is actually part of
it. Then the structure or opposition which kept them apart collapses, as we see
with the terms nature and culture in Derrida’s essay. Ultimately, you can’t
tell which is which, and the idea of binary opposites loses meaning, or is put
into “play” (more on this in the next lecture). This method is called “Deconstruction”
because it is a combination of construction/destruction–the idea is that you
don’t simply construct new system of binaries, with the previously subordinated
term on top, nor do you destroy the old system–rather, you deconstruct the old
system by showing how its basic units of structuration (binary pairs and the
rules for their combination) contradict their own logic.
No comments:
Post a Comment