Archetypical Criticism
Introduction
In the art of painting it is easy to see both structural and representational
elements. A picture is normally a picture "of" some thing: it depicts
or illustrates a "subject" made up of things analogous to
"objects" in sense experience. At the same time there are present
certain elements of pictorial design: what a picture represents is organized
into structural patterns and conventions which are found only in pictures. The
words "content" and "form" are often employed to describe
these complementary aspects of painting. "Realism" connotes an
emphasis on what the picture represents; stylization, whether primitive or
sophisticated, connotes an emphasis on pictorial structure. Extreme realism of
the illusive or trompe l'oeil type is about as far as the
painter can go in one kind of emphasis; abstract, or, more strictly,
non-objective painting is about as far as he can go in the other direction.
(The phrase "non-representational painting" seems to me illogical, a
painting being itself a representation.) The illusive painter however cannot
escape from pictorial conventions, and non-objective painting is still an
imitative art in Aristotle's sense, and so we may say without much fear of
effective contradiction that the whole art of painting lies within a
combination of pictorial "form" or structure and pictorial "content"
or subject.
For some reason the traditions of both practice and theory in Western
painting have weighed down heavily on the imitative or representational end.
Even from Classical painting we have inherited a number of depressing stories,
of birds pecking painted grapes and the like, suggesting that Greek painters
took their greatest pride in concocting trompe l'oeil puzzles.
The development of perspective painting in the Renaissance gave a great
prestige to such skills, the suggesting of three dimensions in a
two-dimensional medium being essentially a trompe l'oeil device.
An eavesdropper in a modern art gallery may easily discover the strength and
persistence of the feeling that to achieve recognizable likeness in a subject,
and to make this likeness the primary thing in his picture, is a moral
obligation on the painter. A good deal of the [131] freakishness of
experimental movements in painting during the last half-century or so has been
due to the energy of its revolt against the tyranny of the representational
fallacy.
An original painter knows, of course, that when the public demands
likeness to an object, it generally wants the exact opposite, likeness to the
pictorial conventions it is familiar with. Hence when he breaks with these
conventions, he is often apt to assert that he is nothing but an eye, that he
merely paints what he sees as he sees it, and the like. His motive in talking
such nonsense is clear enough: he wishes to say that painting is not merely
facile decoration, and involves a difficult conquest of some very real spatial
problems. But this may be freely admitted without agreeing that the formal
cause of a picture is outside the picture, an assertion which would destroy the
whole art if it were taken seriously. What he has actually done is to obey an
obscure but profound impulse to revolt against the conventions established in
his own day, in order to rediscover convention on a deeper level. By breaking
with the Barbizon school, Manet discovered a deeper affinity with Goya and
Velasquez; by breaking with the impressionists, Cezanne discovered a deeper
affinity with Chardin and Masaccio, The possession of originality cannot make
an artist unconventional; it drives him further into convention, obeying the
law of the art itself, which seeks constantly to reshape itself from its own
depths, and which works through its geniuses for metamorphosis, as it works
through minor talents for mutation.
Music affords a refreshing contrast to painting in its critical theory.
When perspective was discovered in painting, music might well have gone in a
similar direction, but in fact the development of representational or
"program" music has been severely restricted. Listeners may still
derive pleasure from hearing external sounds cleverly imitated in music, but no
one asserts that a composer is being a decadent or a charlatan if he fails to
produce such imitations. Nor is it believed that these imitations are prior in
importance to the forms of music itself, still less that they constitute those
forms. The result is that the structural principles of music are clearly
understood, and can be taught even to children.
Suppose, for example, that the present book were an introduction to
musical theory instead of poetics. Then we could begin by isolating, from the
range of audible sounds, the interval of the octave, and explain that the
octave is divided into twelve theoretically [132] equal semitones, forming a
scale of twelve notes which contains potentially all the melodies and harmonies
that the reader of the book will ordinarily hear. Then we could abstract the
two points of repose in this scale, the major and minor common chords, and
explain the system of twenty-four interlocking keys and the conventions of
tonality which require that a piece should normally open and close in the same
key. We could describe the basis of rhythm as an accentuation of every second
or every third beat, and so on through the whole list of rudiments.
Such an outline would give a rational account of the structure of
Western music from 1600 to 1900, and, in a qualified and more flexible but not
essentially different form, of everything that the user of the book would be
accustomed to call music. If we chose, we could lock up all the music outside
the Western tradition in the solitary confinement of a prefatory chapter,
before we got down to serious business. Someone might object that the system of
equal temperament, in which C$ and Db are the same note, is an arbitrary
fiction. Another might object that a composer ought not to be tied down to so
rigidly conventionalized a set of musical elements, and that the resources of
expression in music ought to be as free as the air. A third might object that
we are not talking about music at all: that while the Jupiter Symphony is in C
major and Beethoven's Fifth is in C minor, explaining the difference between
the two keys will give nobody any real notion of the difference between the two
symphonies. All these objectors could be quite safely ignored. Our handbook
would not give the reader a complete musical education, nor would it give an
account of music as it exists in the mind of God or the practice of angels but
it would do for its purposes.
In this book we are attempting to outline a few of the
grammatical rudiments of literary expression, and the elements of it that
correspond to such musical elements as tonality, simple and compound rhythm,
canonical imitation, and the like. The aim is to give a rational account of
some of the structural principles of Western literature in the context of its
Classical and Christian heritage. We are suggesting that the resources of
verbal expression are limited, if that is the word, by the literary equivalents
of rhythm and key, though that does not mean, any more than it means in music,
that its resources are artistically exhaustible. We doubtless have objectors
similar to those just imagined for music, saying [133] that our categories are
artificial, that they do not do justice to the variety of literature, or that
they are not relevant to their own experiences in reading. However, the
question of what the structural principles of literature actually are seems
important enough to discuss; and, as literature is an art of words, it should
be at least as easy to find words to describe them as to find such words as sonata
or fugue in music.
In literature, as in painting, the traditional emphasis in both practice
and theory has been on representation or "lifelikeness." When, for
instance, we pick up a novel of Dickens, our immediate impulse, a habit
fostered in us by all the criticism we know, is to compare it with
"life," whether as lived by us or by Dickens's contemporaries. Then
we meet such characters as Keep or Quilp, and, as neither we nor the Victorians
have ever known anything much "like" these curious monsters, the
method promptly breaks down. Some readers will complain that Dickens has
relapsed into "mere" caricature (as though caricature were easy);
others, more sensibly, simply give up the criterion of lifelikeness and enjoy
the creation for its own sake.
The structural principles of painting are frequently described in terms
of their analogues in plane geometry (or solid, by a further reach of analogy).
A famous letter of Cezanne speaks of the approximation of pictorial form to the
sphere and the cube, and the practice of abstract painters seems to confirm his
point. Geometrical shapes are analogous only to pictorial forms, not by any
means identical with them; the real structural principles of painting are to be
derived, not from an external analogy with something else, but from the
internal analogy of the art itself. The structural principles of literature,
similarly, are to be derived from archetypal and anagogic criticism, the only
kinds that assume a larger context of literature as a whole. But we law in the
first essay that, as the modes of fiction move from the mythical to the low
mimetic and ironic, they approach a point of extreme "realism" or
representative likeness to life. It follows that the mythical mode, the stories
about gods, in which characters have the greatest possible power of action, is
the most abstract and conventionalized of all literary modes, just as the
corresponding modes in other arts - religious Byzantine painting, for example -
show the highest degree of stylization in their structure. Hence the structural
principles of literature are as closely related to mythology and comparative
religion as [134] those of painting are to geometry. In this essay we shall be
using the symbolism of the Bible, and to a lesser extent Classical mythology,
as a grammar of literary archetypes.
In the Egyptian tale of The Two Brothers, thought to be the source of
the Potiphar's wife story in the Joseph legend, an elder brother's wife
attempts to seduce an unmarried younger brother who lives with them, and, when
he resists her, accuses him of attempting to rape her. The younger brother is
then forced to run away, with the enraged elder brother in pursuit. So far, the
incidents reproduce more or less credible facts of life. Then the younger
brother prays to Ra for assistance, pleading the justice of his cause; Ra
places a large lake between him and his brother, and, in a burst of divine
exuberance, fills it full of crocodiles. This incident is no more a fictional
episode than anything that has preceded it, nor is it less logically related
than any other episode to the plot as a whole. But it has given up the external
analogy to "life": this, we say, is the kind of thing that happens
only in stories. The Egyptian tale has acquired, then, in its mythical episode,
an abstractly literary quality; and, as the story-teller could just as easily
have solved his little problem in a more "realistic" way, it appears
that literature in Egypt, like the other arts, preferred a certain degree of
stylization.
Similarly, a medieval saint with a huge decorated halo around his head
may look like an old man, but the mythical feature, the halo, both imparts a
more abstract structure to the painting and gives the saint the kind of
appearance that one sees only in pictures. In primitive societies, a
flourishing development in myth and folk tale usually accompanies a taste for
geometrical ornament in the plastic arts. In our tradition we have a place for
verisimilitude, for human experience skilfully and consistently imitated. The occasional
hoaxes in which fiction is presented, or even accepted, as fact, such as
Defoe's Journal of the Plague Year or Samuel Butler's The
Fair Haven, correspond to trompe l'oeil illusions in
painting. At the other extreme we have myths, or abstract fictional designs in
which gods and other such beings do whatever they like, which in practice means
whatever the story-teller likes. The return of irony to myth that we noted in
the first essay is contemporary with, and parallel to, abstraction, expressionism,
cubism, and similar efforts in painting to emphasize the self-contained
pictorial structure. Sixty years ago, Bernard Shaw stressed the social
significance of the themes in Ibsen's plays and his own. Today, [135] Mr. Eliot
calls our attention to the Alcestis archetype in The Cocktail Party,
to the Ion archetype in The Confidential Clerk. The former is of
the age of Manet and Degas; the latter of the age of Braque and Graham
Sutherland.
We begin our study of archetypes, then, with a world of myth, an abstract
or purely literary world of fictional and thematic design, unaffected by canons
of plausible adaptation to familiar experience. In terms of narrative, myth is
the imitation of actions near or at the conceivable limits of desire. The gods
enjoy beautiful women, fight one another with prodigious strength, comfort and
assist man, or else watch his miseries from the height of their immortal
freedom. The fact that myth operates at the top level of human desire does not
mean that it necessarily presents its world as attained or attainable by human
beings. In terms of meaning or dianoia, myth is the same world
looked at as an area or field of activity, bearing in mind our principle that
the meaning or pattern of poetry is a structure of imagery with conceptual
implications. The world of mythical imagery is usually represented by the
conception of heaven or Paradise in religion, and it is apocalyptic, in the
sense of that word already explained, a world of total metaphor, in which every
thing is potentially identical with everything else, as though it were all
inside a single infinite body.
Realism, or the art of verisimilitude, evokes the response "How
like that is to what we know!" When what is written is like what is known,
we have an art of extended or implied simile. And as realism is an art of
implicit simile, myth is an art of implicit metaphorical identity. The word
"sun-god," with a hyphen used in stead of a predicate, is a pure
ideogram, in Pound's terminology, or literal metaphor, in ours. In myth we see
the structural principles of literature isolated; in realism we see the same
structural principles (not similar ones) fitting into a context of
plausibility. (Similarly in music, a piece by Purcell and a piece by Benjamin
Britten may not be in the least like each other, but if they are both in D
major their tonality will be the same.) The presence of a mythical structure in
realistic fiction, however, poses certain technical problems for making it
plausible, and the devices used in solving these problems may be given the
general name of displacement.
Myth, then, is one extreme of literary design; naturalism is the other,
and in between lies the whole area of romance, using that term to mean, not the
historical mode of the first essay, but the [136] tendency, noted later in the
same essay, to displace myth in a human direction and yet, in contrast to
"realism," to conventionalize content in an idealized direction. The
central principle of displacement is that what can be metaphorically identified
in a myth can only be linked in romance by some form of simile: analogy,
significant association, incidental accompanying imagery, and the like. In a
myth we can have a sun-god or a tree-god; in a romance we may have a person who
is significantly associated with the sun or trees. In more realistic modes the
association becomes less significant and more a matter of incidental, even
coincidental or accidental, imagery. In the dragon-killing legend of the St.
George and Perseus family, of which more hereafter, a country under an old
feeble king is terrorized by a dragon who eventually demands the king's
daughter, but is slain by the hero. This seems to be a romantic analogy
(perhaps also, in this case, a descendant) of a myth of a waste land restored
to life by a fertility god. In the myth, then, the dragon and the old king
would be identified. We can in fact concentrate the myth still further into an
Oedipus fantasy in which the hero is not the old king's son-in-law but his son,
and the rescued damsel the hero's mother. If the story were a private dream
such identifications would be made as a matter of course. But to make it a
plausible, symmetrical, and morally acceptable story a good deal of
displacement is necessary, and it is only after a comparative study of the story
type has been made that the metaphorical structure within it begins to emerge.
In Hawthorne's The Marble Faun the statue which gives
the story that name is so insistently associated with a character named
Donatello that a reader would have to be unusually dull or inattentive to miss
the point that Donatello "is" the statue. Later on we meet a girl
named Hilda, of singular purity and gentleness, who lives in a tower surrounded
by doves. The doves are very fond of her; another character calls her his
"dove," and remarks indicating some special affinity with doves are
made about her by both author and characters. If we were to say that Hilda is a
dove-goddess like Venus, identified with her doves, we should not be reading
the story quite accurately in its own mode; we should be translating it into
straight myth. But to recognize how close Hawthorne is to myth here is not
unfair. That is, we recognize that The Marble Faunis not a typical
low mimetic fiction: it is dominated by an interest that looks back to fictional
romance and forward to the [137] ironic mythical writers of the next century to
Kafka, for instance, or Cocteau. This interest is often called allegory, but
probably Hawthorne himself was right in calling it romance. We can see how this
interest tends toward abstraction in character-drawing, and if we know no other
canons than low mimetic ones, we complain of this.
Or, again, we have, in myth, the story of Proserpine, who disappears
into the underworld for six months of every year. The pure myth is clearly one
of death and revival; the story as we have it is slightly displaced, but the
mythical pattern is easy to see. The same structural element often recurs in
Shakespearean comedy, where it has to be adapted to a roughly high mimetic
level of credibility. Hero in Much Ado is dead enough to have
a funeral song, and plausible explanations are postponed until after the end of
the play. Imogen in Cymbeline has an assumed name and an empty
grave, but she too gets some funeral obsequies. But the story of Hermione and
Perdita is so close to the Demeter and Proserpine myth that hardly any serious
pretence of plausible explanations is made. Hermione, after her disappearance,
returns once as a ghost in a dream, and her coming to life from a statue, a
displacement of the Pygmalion myth, is said to require an awakening of faith,
even though, on one level of plausibility, she has not been a statue at all,
and nothing has taken place except a harmless deception. We notice how much
more abstractly mythical a thematic writer can be than a fictional one:
Spenser's Florimell, for instance, disappears under the sea for the winter with
no questions asked, leaving a "snowy lady" in her place and returning
with a great outburst of spring floods at the end of the fourth book.
In the low mimetic, we recognize the same structural pattern of the
death and revival of the heroine when Esther Summerson gets smallpox, or Lorna
Doone is shot at her marriage altar. But we are getting closer to the
conventions of realism, and although Lorna's eyes are "dim with
death," we know that the author does not really mean death if he is
planning to revive her. Here again it is interesting to compare The
Marble Faun, where there is so much about sculptors and the relation of
statues to living people that we almost expect some kind of denouement like
that of The Winter's Tale. Hilda mysteriously disappears, and
during her absence her lover, the sculptor Kenyon, digs out of the earth a
[138] statue that he associates with Hilda. After that Hilda returns, with a
plausible reason eventually assigned for her absence, but not without some
rather pointed and petulant remarks from Hawthorne himself to the effect that
he has no interest in concocting plausible explanations, and that he wishes his
reading public would give him a bit more freedom. Yet Hawthorne's inhibitions
seem to be at least in part self-imposed, as we can see if we turn to
Poe's Ligeia, where the straight mythical death and revival pattern
is given without apology. Poe is clearly a more radical abstractionist than
Hawthorne, which is one reason why his influence on our century is more
immediate.
This affinity between the mythical and the abstractly literary
illuminates many aspects of fiction, especially the more popular fiction which
is realistic enough to be plausible in its incidents and yet romantic enough to
be a "good story," which means a clearly designed one. The
introduction of an omen or portent, or the device of making a whole story the
fulfilment of a prophecy given at the beginning, is an example. Such a device
suggests, in its existential projection, a conception of ineluctable fate or
hidden omnipotent will. Actually, it is a piece of pure literary design, giving
the beginning some symmetrical relationship with the end, and the only
ineluctable will involved is that of the author. Hence we often find it even in
writers not temperamentally much in sympathy with the portentous. In Anna
Karenina, for instance, the death of the railway porter in the opening book
is accepted by Anna as an omen for herself. Similarly, if we find portents and
omens in Sophocles, they are there primarily because they fit the structure of
his type of dramatic tragedy, and prove nothing about any clear-cut beliefs in
fate held by either dramatist or audience.
We have, then, three organizations of myths and archetypal symbols in
literature. First, there is undisplaced myth, generally concerned with gods or
demons, and which takes the form of two contrasting worlds of total
metaphorical identification, one desirable and the other undesirable. These
worlds are often identified with the existential heavens and hells of the
religions contemporary with such literature. These two forms of metaphorical
organization we call the apocalyptic and the demonic respectively. Second, we
have the general tendency we have called romantic, the tendency to suggest
implicit mythical patterns in a world more closely [139] associated with human
experience. Third, we have the tendency of "realism" (my distaste for
this inept term is reflected in the quotation marks) to throw the emphasis on
content and representation rather than on the shape of the story. Ironic
literature begins with realism and tends toward myth, its mythical patterns
being as a rule more suggestive of the demonic than of the apocalyptic, though
sometimes it simply continues the romantic tradition of stylization. Hawthorne,
Poe, Conrad, Hardy and Virginia Woolf all provide examples.
In looking at a picture, we may stand close to it and analyze the
details of brush work and palette knife. This corresponds roughly to the
rhetorical analysis of the new critics in literature. At a little distance
back, the design comes into clearer view, and we study rather the content
represented: this is the best distance for realistic Dutch pictures, for
example, where we are in a sense reading the picture. The further back we go,
the more conscious we are of the organizing design. At a great distance from,
say, a Madonna, we can see nothing but the archetype of the Madonna, a large
centripetal blue mass with a contrasting point of interest at its center. In
the criticism of literature, too, we often have to "stand back" from
the poem to see its archetypal organization. If we "stand back" from
Spenser's Mutabilitie Cantoes, we see a background of ordered
circular light and a sinister black mass thrusting up into the lower foreground
much the same archetypal shape that we see in the opening of the Book of Job.
If we "stand back" from the beginning of the fifth act of Hamlet,
we see a grave opening on the stage, the hero, his enemy, and the heroine
descending into it, followed by a fatal struggle in the upper world. If we
"stand back" from a realistic novel such as Tolstoy's Resurrectionor
Zola's Germinal, we can see the mythopoeic designs indicated by
those titles. Other examples will be given in what follows.
We proceed to give an account first of the structure of imagery,
or dianoia, of the two undisplaced worlds, the apocalyptic and the
demonic, drawing heavily on the Bible, the main source for undisplaced myth in
our tradition. Then we go on to the two intermediate structures of imagery, and
finally to the generic narratives or mythoi which are these
structures of imagery in movement. [140]
Theory of Archetypal Meaning (1): Apocalyptic Imagery
Let us proceed according to the general scheme of the game of Twenty
Questions, or, if we prefer, of the Great Chain of Being, the traditional
scheme for classifying sense data.
The apocalyptic world, the heaven of religion, presents, in the first
place, the categories of reality in the forms of human desire, as indicated by
the forms they assume under the work of human civilization. The form imposed by
human work and desire on the vegetable world, for instance, is
that of the garden, the farm, the grove, or the park. The human form of
the animal world is a world of domesticated animals, of which
the sheep has a traditional priority in both Classical and Christian metaphor.
The human form of the mineral world, the form into which human
work transforms stone, is the city. The city, the garden, and the sheepfold are
the organizing metaphors of the Bible and of most Christian symbolism, and they
are brought into complete metaphorical identification in the book explicitly
called the Apocalypse or Revelation, which has been carefully designed to form
an undisplaced mythical conclusion for the Bible as a whole. From our point of
view this means that the Biblical Apocalypse is our grammar of apocalyptic
imagery.
Each of these three categories, the city, the garden, and the sheepfold,
is, by the principle of archetypal metaphor dealt with in the previous essay,
and which we remember is the concrete universal, identical with the others and
with each individual within it. Hence the divine and human worlds are,
similarly, identical with the sheepfold, city and garden, and the social and
individual aspects of each are identical. Thus the apocalyptic world of the
Bible presents the following pattern:
divine world = society of gods = One God
human world = society of men = One Man
animal world = sheepfold = One Lamb
vegetable world = garden or park = One Tree (of Life)
mineral world = city = One Building, Temple, Stone
The conception "Christ" unites all these categories in
identity: Christ is both the one God and the one Man, the Lamb of God, the tree
of life, or vine of which we are the branches, the stone [141] which the
builders rejected, and the rebuilt temple which is identical with his risen
body. The religious and poetic identifications differ in intention only, the
former being existential and the latter metaphorical. In medieval criticism the
difference was of little importance, and the word "figura," as
applied to the identification of a symbol with Christ, usually implies both
kinds.
Now let us expand this pattern a little. In Christianity the concrete
universal is applied to the divine world in the form of the Trinity.
Christianity insists that, whatever dislocations of customary mental processes
may be involved, God is three persons and yet one God. The conceptions of
person and substance represent a few of the difficulties in extending metaphor
to logic. In pure metaphor, of course, the unity of God could apply to five or
seventeen or a million divine persons as easily as three, and we may find the
divine concrete universal in poetry outside the Trinitarian orbit. When Zeus
remarks, at the beginning of the eighth book of the Iliad, that he can pull the
whole chain of being up into himself when ever he likes, we can see that for
Homer there was some conception of a double perspective in Olympus, where a
group of squabbling deities may at any time suddenly compose into the form of a
single divine will. In Virgil we first meet a malicious and spoiled Juno, but
the comment of Aeneas to his men a few lines later on, "deus dabit his
quoque finem," indicates that a similar double perspective existed for
him. We may compare perhaps the Book of Job, where Job and his friends are much
too devout for it ever to occur to them that Job could have suffered so as a
result of a half-jocular bet between God and Satan. There is a sense in which
they are right, and the information given to the reader about Satan in heaven
wrong. Satan is dropped out of the end of the poem, and whatever rewritings may
be responsible for this, it is still difficult to see how the final
enlightenment of Job could ever have returned completely from the conception of
a single divine will to the mood of the opening scene.
As for human society, the metaphor that we are all members of one body
has organized most political theory from Plato to our own day. Milton's "A
Commonwealth ought to be but as one huge Christian personage, one mighty
growth, and stature of an honest man" belongs to a Christianized version
of this metaphor, in which, as in the doctrine of the Trinity, the full
metaphorical statement "Christ is God and Man" is orthodox, and the
Arian and Docetic [142] statements in terms of simile or likeness condemned as
heretical. Hobbes's Leviathan, with its original frontispiece
depicting a number of mannikins inside the body of a single giant, has also
some connection with the same type of identification. Plato's Republic, in
which the reason, will, and desire of the individual appear as the
philosopher-king, guards, and artisans of the state, is also founded on this
metaphor, which in fact we still use whenever we speak of a group or aggregate
of human beings as a "body."
In sexual symbolism, of course, it is still easier to employ the
"one flesh" metaphor of two bodies made into the same body by love.
Donne's The Extasie is one of the many poems organized on this
image, and Shakespeare's Phoenix and the Turtle makes great
play with the outrage done to the "reason" by such identity. Themes
of loyalty, hero-worship, faithful followers, and the like also employ the same
metaphor.
The animal and vegetable worlds are identified with each other, and with
the divine and human worlds as well, in the Christian doctrine of
transubstantiation, in which the essential human forms of the vegetable world,
food and drink, the harvest and the vintage, the bread and the wine, are the
body and blood of the Lamb who is also Man and God, and in whose body we exist
as in a city or temple. Here again the orthodox doctrine insists on metaphor as
against simile, and here again the conception of substance illustrates the
struggles of logic to digest the metaphor. It is clear from the opening of the
Laws that the symposium had something of the same communion symbolism for
Plato. It would be hard to find a simpler or more vivid image of human
civilization, where man attempts to surround nature and put it inside his
(social) body, than the sacramental meal.
The conventional honors accorded the sheep in the animal world provide
us with the central archetype of pastoral imagery, as well as with such
metaphors as "pastor" and "flock" in religion. The metaphor
of the king as the shepherd of his people goes back to ancient Egypt. Perhaps
the use of this particular convention is due to the fact that, being stupid,
affectionate, gregarious, and easily stampeded, the societies formed by sheep
are most like human ones. But of course in poetry any other animal would do as
well if the poet's audience were prepared for it: at the opening of the
Brihadaranyaka Upanishad, for instance, the sacrificial horse, whose body
contains the whole universe, is treated in the same way that a Christian poet
[143] would treat the Lamb of God. Of birds, too, the dove has traditionally
represented the universal concord or love both of Venus and of the Christian
Holy Spirit. Identifications of gods with animals or plants and of those again
with human society form the basis of totemic symbolism. Certain types of
etiological folk tale, the stories of how supernatural beings were turned into
the animals and plants that we know, represent an attentuated form of the same
type of metaphor, and survive as the "metamorphosis" archetype
familiar from Ovid.
Similar flexibility is possible with vegetable images. Elsewhere in the
Bible the leaves or fruit of the tree of life are used as communion symbols in
place of the bread and wine. Or the concrete universal may be applied not
simply to a tree but to a single fruit or flower. In the West the rose has a
traditional priority among apocalyptic flowers: the use of the rose as a
communion symbol in the Paradiso comes readily to mind, and
in the first book of The Faerie Queene the emblem of St. George, a
red cross on a white ground, is connected not only with the risen body of
Christ and the sacramental symbolism which accompanies it, but with the union
of the red and white roses in the Tudor dynasty. In the East the lotus or the
Chinese "golden flower" often occupied the place of the rose, and in
German Romanticism the blue cornflower enjoyed a brief vogue.
The identity of the human body and the vegetable world gives us the
archetype of Arcadian imagery, of Marvell's green world, of Shakespeare's
forest comedies, of the world of Robin Hood and other green men who lurk in the
forests of romance, these last the counterparts in romance of the metaphorical
myth of the tree-god. In Marvell's The Garden we meet a
further but still conventional extension in the identification of the human
soul with a bird sitting in the branches of the tree of life. The olive tree
and its oil has supplied another identification in the "anointed"
ruler.
The city, whether called Jerusalem or not, is apocalyptically identical
with a single building or temple, a "house of many mansions," of
which individuals are "lively stones," to use another New Testament
phrase. The human use of the inorganic world involves the highway or road as
well as the city with its streets, and the metaphor of the "way" is
inseparable from all quest-literature, whether explicitly Christian as in The Pilgrim's Progress or not. To this [144]
category also belong geometrical and architectural images: the tower and the
winding stairway of Dante and Yeats, Jacob's ladder, the ladder of the
Neo-platonic love poets, the ascending spiral or cornucopia, the "stately
pleasure dome" that Kubla Khan decreed, the cross and quincunx patterns
which Browne sought in every corner of art and nature, the circle as the emblem
of eternity, Vaughan's "ring of pure and endless light," and so on.
On the archetypal level proper, where poetry is an artifact of human
civilization, nature is the container of man. On the anagogic level, man is the
container of nature, and his cities and gardens are no longer little hollowings
on the surface of the earth, but the forms of a human universe. Hence in
apocalyptic symbolism we cannot confine man only to his two natural elements of
earth and air, and, in going from one level to the other, symbolism must, like
Tamino in The Magic Flute, pass the ordeals of water and
fire. Poetic symbolism usually puts fire just above man's life in this world,
and water just below it. Dante had to pass through a ring of fire and the river
of Eden to go from the mountain of purgatory, which is still on the surface of
our own world, to Paradise or the apocalyptic world proper. The imagery of
light and fire surrounding the angels in the Bible, the tongues of flame
descending at Pentecost, and the coal of fire applied to the mouth of Isaiah by
the seraph, associates fire with a spiritual or angelic world midway between
the human and the divine. In Classical mythology the story of Prometheus
indicates a similar provenance for fire, as does the association of Zeus with
the thunderbolt or fire of lightning. In short, heaven in the sense of the sky,
containing the fiery bodies of sun, moon, and stars, is usually identified
with, or thought of as the passage to, the heaven of the apocalyptic world.
Hence all our other categories can be identified with fire or thought of
as burning. The appearance of the Judaeo-Christian deity in fire, surrounded by
angels of fire (seraphim) and light (cherubim), needs only to be mentioned. The
burning animal of the ritual of sacrifice, the incorporating of an animal body
in a communion between divine and human worlds, modulates into all the imagery connected
with the fire and smoke of the altar, ascending incense, and the like. The
burning man is represented in the saint's halo and the king's crown, both of
which are analogues of the sun-god: one may compare also the "burning
babe" of Southwell's Christmas [145] poem. The image of the burning bird
appears in the legendary phoenix. The tree of life may also be a burning tree,
the unconsumed burning bush of Moses, the candlestick of Jewish ritual, or the
"rosy cross" of later occultism. In alchemy the vegetable, mineral,
and water worlds are identified in its rose, stone, and elixir; flower and
jewel archetypes are identified in the "jewel in the lotus" of the
Buddhist prayer. The links between fire, intoxicating wine, and the hot red
blood of animals are also common.
The identification of the city with fire explains why the city of God in
the Apocalypse is presented as a glowing mass of gold and precious stones, each
stone presumably burning with a hard gem-like flame. For in apocalyptic
symbolism the fiery bodies of heaven, sun, moon, and stars, are all inside the
universal divine and human body. The symbolism of alchemy is apocalyptic
symbolism of the same type: the center of nature, the gold and jewels hidden in
the earth, is eventually to be united to its circumference in the sun, moon,
and stars of the heavens; the center of the spiritual world, the soul of man,
is united to its circumference in God. Hence there is a close association
between the purifying of the human soul and the transmuting of earth to gold,
not only literal gold but the fiery quintessential gold of which the heavenly
bodies are made. The golden tree with its mechanical bird in Sailing to
Byzantium identifies vegetable and mineral worlds in a form reminiscent of
alchemy.
Water, on the other hand, traditionally belongs to a realm of existence
below human life, the state of chaos or dissolution which follows ordinary
death, or the reduction to the inorganic. Hence the soul frequently crosses
water or sinks into it at death. In apocalyptic symbolism we have the
"water of life," the fourfold river of Eden which reappears in the
City of God, and is represented in ritual by baptism. According to Ezekiel the
return of this river turns the sea fresh, which is apparently why the author of
Revelation says that in the apocalypse there is no more sea. Apocalyptically,
therefore, water circulates in the universal body like the blood in the
individual body. Perhaps we should say "is held within" instead of
"circulates," to avoid the anachronism of connecting a knowledge of
the circulation of the blood with Biblical themes. For centuries, of course,
the blood was one of four "humors," or bodily liquids, just as the
river of life was traditionally fourfold. [146]
Opposed to apocalyptic symbolism
is the presentation of the world that desire totally rejects: the world of the
nightmare and the scapegoat, of bondage and pain and confusion; the world as it
is before the human imagination begins to work on it and before any image of
human desire, such as the city or the garden, has been solidly established; the
world also of perverted or wasted work, ruins and catacombs, instruments of
torture and monuments of folly. And just as apocalyptic imagery in poetry is
closely associated with a religious heaven, so its dialectic opposite is
closely linked with an existential hell, like Dante's Inferno, or with the hell that man creates on earth, as in 1984, No Exit, and Darkness at Noon, where the titles of the last two speak for themselves. Hence one of
the central themes of demonic imagery is parody, the mocking of the exuberant
play of art by suggesting its imitation in terms of "real life."
The demonic divine world largely personifies the vast, menacing, stupid
powers of nature as they appear to a technologically undeveloped society.
Symbols of heaven in such a world tend to become associated with the
inaccessible sky, and the central idea that crystallizes from it is the idea of
inscrutable fate or external necessity. The machinery of fate is administered
by a set of remote invisible gods, whose freedom and pleasure are ironic
because they exclude man, and who intervene in human affairs chiefly to
safeguard their own prerogatives. They demand sacrifices, punish presumption,
and enforce obedience to natural and moral law as an end in itself. Here we are
not trying to describe, for instance, the gods in Greek tragedy: we are trying
to isolate the sense of human remoteness and futility in relation to the divine
order which is only one element among others in most tragic visions of life,
though an essential one in all. In later ages poets become much more outspoken
about this view of divinity: Blake's Nobodaddy, Shelley's Jupiter, Swinburne's
"supreme evil, God," Hardy's befuddled Will, and Housman's
"brute and blackguard" are examples.
The demonic human world is a society held together by a kind of
molecular tension of egos, a loyalty to the group or the leader which
diminishes the individual, or, at best, contrasts his pleasure with his duty or
honor. Such a society is an endless source of tragic [147] dilemmas like those
of Hamlet and Antigone. In the apocalyptic conception of human life we found
three kinds of fulfilment: individual, sexual, and social. In the sinister
human world one individual pole is the tyrant-leader, inscrutable, ruthless,
melancholy, and with an insatiable will, who commands loyalty only if he is
egocentric enough to represent the collective ego of his followers. The other
pole is represented by the pharmakos or sacrificed victim, who
has to be killed to strengthen the others. In the most concentrated form of the
demonic parody, the two become the same. The ritual of the killing of the
divine king in Frazer, whatever it may be in anthropology, is in literary
criticism the demonic or undisplaced radical form of tragic and ironic
structures.
In religion the spiritual world is a reality distinct from the physical
world. In poetry the physical or actual is opposed, not to the spiritually
existential, but to the hypothetical. We met in the first essay the principle
that the transmutation of act into mime, the advance from acting out a rite to
playing at the rite, is one of the central features of the development from
savagery into culture. It is easy to see a mimesis of conflict in tennis and
football, but, precisely for that very reason, tennis and football players
represent a culture superior to the culture of student duellists and
gladiators. The turning of literal act into play is a fundamental form of the
liberalizing of life which appears in more intellectual levels as liberal
education, the release of fact into imagination. It is consistent with this
that the Eucharist symbolism of the apocalyptic world, the metaphorical
identification of vegetable, animal, human, and divine bodies, should have the
imagery of cannibalism for its demonic parody. Dante's last vision of human
hell is of Ugolino gnawing his tormentor's skull; Spenser's last major
allegorical vision is of Serena stripped and prepared for a cannibal feast. The
imagery of cannibalism usually includes, not only images of torture and
mutilation, but of what is technically known as sparagmos or
the tearing apart of the sacrificial body, an image found in the myths of
Osiris, Orpheus, and Pentheus. The cannibal giant or ogre of folk tales, who
enters literature as Polyphemus, belongs here, as does a long series of
sinister dealings with flesh and blood from the story of Thyestes to Shylock's
bond. Here again the form described by Frazer as the historically original form
is in literary criticism the radical demonic form. Flaubert's Salammbo is
a study [148] of demonic imagery which was thought in its day to be archaeological
but turned out to be prophetic.
The demonic erotic relation becomes a fierce destructive passion that
works against loyalty or frustrates the one who possesses it. It is generally
symbolized by a harlot, witch, siren, or other tantalizing female, a physical
object of desire which is sought as a possession and therefore can never be
possessed. The demonic parody of marriage, or the union of two souls in one
flesh, may take the form of hermaphroditism, incest (the most common form), or
homosexuality. The social relation is that of the mob, which is essentially
human society looking for a pharmakos, and the mob is often identified
with some sinister animal image such as the hydra, Virgil's Fama, or its
development in Spenser's Blatant Beast.
The other worlds can be briefly summarized. The animal world is
portrayed in terms of monsters or beasts of prey. The wolf, the traditional
enemy of the sheep, the tiger, the vulture, the cold and earth-bound serpent,
and the dragon are all common. In the Bible, where the demonic society is
represented by Egypt and Babylon, the rulers of each are identified with
monstrous beasts: Nebuchadnezzar turns into a beast in Daniel, and Pharaoh is
called a river-dragon by Ezekiel. The dragon is especially appropriate because it
is not only monstrous and sinister but fabulous, and so represents the
paradoxical nature of evil as a moral fact and an eternal negation. In the
Apocalypse the dragon is called "the beast that was, and is not, and yet
is."
The vegetable world is a sinister forest like the ones we meet in Comus
or the opening of the Inferno, or a heath, which from Shakespeare to Hardy has
been associated with tragic destiny, or a wilderness like that of
Browning's Childe Roland or Eliot's Waste Land. Or it may be a sinister enchanted garden like that of Circe and its
Renaissance descendants in Tasso and Spenser. In the Bible the waste land
appears in its concrete universal form in the tree of death, the tree of
forbidden knowledge in Genesis, the barren fig-tree of the Gospels, and the
cross. The stake, with the hooded heretic, the black man or the witch attached
to it, is the burning tree and body of the infernal world. Scaffolds, gallows,
stocks, pillories, whips, and birch rods are or could be modulations. The
contrast of the tree of life and the tree of death is beautifully expressed in
Yeats's poem The Two Trees. [149]
The inorganic world may remain in its unworked form of deserts, rocks,
and waste land. Cities of destruction and dreadful night belong here, and the great
ruins of pride, from the tower of Babel to the mighty works of Ozymandias.
Images of perverted work be long here too: engines of torture, weapons of war,
armor, and images of a dead mechanism which, because it does not humanize
nature, is unnatural as well as inhuman. Corresponding to the temple or One
Building of the apocalypse, we have the prison or dungeon, the sealed furnace
of heat without light, like the City of Dis in Dante. Here too are the sinister
counterparts of geometrical images: the sinister spiral (the maelstrom,
whirlpool, or Charybdis), the sinister cross, and the sinister circle, the
wheel of fate or fortune. The identification of the circle with the serpent,
conventionally a demonic animal, gives us the ouroboros, or serpent with its
tail in its mouth. Corresponding to the apocalyptic way or straight road, the
highway in the desert for God prophesied by Isaiah, we have in this world the
labyrinth or maze, the image of lost direction, often with a monster at its
heart like the Minotaur. The labyrinthine wanderings of Israel in the desert,
repeated by Jesus when in the company of the devil (or "wild beasts,"
according to Mark), fit the same pattern. The labyrinth can also be a sinister
forest, as in Comus. The catacombs are effectively used in the same context
in The Marble Faun, and of course in a further
concentration of metaphor, the maze would become the winding entrails inside
the sinister monster himself.
The world of fire is a world of malignant demons like the
will-o'-the-wisps, or spirits broken from hell, and it appears in this world in
the form of the auto da fe as mentioned, or such
burning cities as Sodom. It is in contrast to the purgatorial or cleansing
fire, like the fiery furnace in Daniel. The world of water is the water of
death, often identified with spilled blood, as in the Passion and in Dante's
symbolic figure of history, and above all the "unplumbed, salt, estranging
sea," which absorbs all rivers in this world, but disappears in the
apocalypse in favor of a circulation of fresh water. In the Bible the sea and
the animal monster are identified in the figure of the leviathan, a sea-monster
also identified with the social tyrannies of Babylon and Egypt. [150]
Most imagery in poetry has of
course to deal with much less extreme worlds than the two which are usually
projected as the eternal unchanging worlds of heaven and hell. Apocalyptic
imagery is appropriate to the mythical mode, and demonic imagery to the ironic
mode in the late phase in which it returns to myth. In the other three modes
these two structures operate dialectically, pulling the reader toward the
metaphorical and mythical undisplaced core of the work. We should therefore
expect three intermediate structures of imagery, corresponding roughly to the
romantic, high mimetic, and low mimetic modes. We shall give little attention to
high mimetic imagery, however, in order to preserve the simpler pattern of the
romantic and "realistic" tendencies within the two undisplaced
structures given at the beginning of this essay.
These three structures are less rigorously metaphorical, and are rather
significant constellations of images, which, when found together, make up what
is often called, somewhat helplessly, "atmosphere." The mode of
romance presents an idealized world: in romance heroes are brave, heroines
beautiful, villains villainous, and the frustrations, ambiguities, and
embarrassments of ordinary life are made little of. Hence its imagery presents
a human counterpart of the apocalyptic world which we may call the analogy of
innocence. It is best known to us, not from the age of romance itself, but from
later romanticizings: Comus, The Tempest, and the third book of The
Faerie Queene in the
Renaissance; Blake's songs of innocence and "Beulah" imagery,
Keats's Endymion and Shelley's Epipsychidion in the Romantic period proper.
In the analogy of innocence the divine or spiritual figures are usually
parental, wise old men with magical powers like Prospero, or friendly guardian
spirits like Raphael before Adam's fall. Among the human figures children are
prominent, and so is the virtue most closely associated with childhood and the
state of innocence chastity, a virtue which in this structure of imagery
usually includes virginity. In Comus the Lady's chastity is, like
Prosperous wisdom, associated with magic, as is the invincible chastity of
Spenser's Britomart It is easiest to associate with young women Dante's Matelda
and Shakespeare's Miranda are examples but male chastity is important too, as
the Grail romances show. Sir Galahad's [151] remark in Tennyson about his
purity of heart giving him tenfold strength is consistent with the imagery of
the world he belongs in. Fire in the innocent world is usually a purifying
symbol, a world of flame that none but the perfectly chaste can pass, as in
Spenser's castle of Busirane, the refining fire at the top of Dante's
purgatory, and the flaming sword that keeps the fallen Adam and Eve away from
Paradise. In the story of the sleeping beauty, which belongs here, the wall of
flame is replaced by one of thorns and brambles: Wagner's Die Walkure, however, retains the fire, to the discomposure of stage managers. The
moon, the coolest and hence most chaste of all the fiery heavenly bodies, has a
special importance for this world.
Of animals, the most obvious are the pastoral sheep and lambs, along with
the horses and hounds of romance, in their gentler aspects of fidelity and
devotion. The unicorn, the traditional emblem of chastity and the lover of
virgins, has an honored place here; so does the dolphin, whose association with
Arion makes him the innocent contrast to the devouring leviathan; and also, for
its humility and submissiveness, a very different animal the ass. The dramatic
festival of the ass, no less than that of the Boy Bishop, belongs to this
structure of imagery, and when Shakespeare put an ass's head in Fairyland he
was not doing something unique, as Robinson's poem implies, but following a
tradition that goes back to the transformed Lucius listening to the story of
Cupid and Psyche in Apuleius. Birds, butterflies (for this is Psyche's world,
and Psyche means butterfly), and spirits with their qualities, like Ariel and
Hudson's Rima, are other naturalized denizens.
The paradisal garden and the tree of life belong in the apocalyptic
structure, as we saw, but the garden of Eden itself, as presented in the Bible
and Milton, belongs rather to this one, and Dante puts it just below his
Paradiso. Spenser's Gardens of Adonis, from which the attendant spirit inComus comes, are parallel, along with all the medieval developments of
the theme of the locus amoenus. Of special significance is the
symbol of the body of the Virgin as a hortus
conclusus, derived from the
Song of Songs. A romantic counterpart to the tree of life appears in the
magician's life-giving wand, and such parallel symbols as the blossoming rod
in Tannhauser.
Cities are more alien to the pastoral and rural spirit of this world,
and the tower and the castle, with an occasional cottage or hermitage, are the
chief images of habitation. Water symbolism features [152] chiefly fountains and
pools, fertilizing rains, and an occasional stream separating a man from a
woman and so preserving the chastity of each, like the river of Lethe in Dante.
The opening rose-garden episode of Burnt
Nortongives a brief but
extraordinarily complete summary of the symbols of the analogy of innocence;
one may also compare the second section of Auden's Kairos and Logos.
The innocent world is neither totally alive, like the apocalyptic one,
nor mostly dead, like ours: it is an animistic world, full of elemental
spirits. All the characters of Comus are elemental spirits except
the Lady and her brothers, and the connections of Ariel with air-spirits, of
Puck with fire-spirits (Burton says of fire-spirits that "we commonly call
them Pucks"), and of Caliban with earth-spirits are clear enough. In
Spenser we find Florimell and Marinell, whose names indicate that they are
spirits of flowers and water, a Proserpine and an Adonis. Often, too, as
in Comus and the Nativity Ode, innocent or unfallen nature,
nature as a divinely sanctioned order, is represented by the inaudible harmony
of the music of the spheres.
Just as the organizing ideas of romance are chastity and magic, so the
organizing ideas of the high mimetic area seem to be love and form. And as the
field of romantic images may be called an analogy of innocence, so the field of
high mimetic imagery may be called an analogy of nature and reason. We find
here the emphasis on cynosure or centripetal gaze, and the tendency to idealize
the human representatives of the divine and the spiritual world, which are
characteristic of the high mimetic. Divinity hedges the king and the Courtly
Love mistress is a goddess; love of both is an educating and informing power
which brings one into unity with the spiritual and divine worlds. The fire of
the angelic world blazes in the king's crown and the lady's eyes. The animals
are those of proud beauty: the eagle and the lion stand for the vision of the
royal by the loyal, the horse and falcon for "chivalry" or the
aristocracy on horseback; the peacock and the swan are the birds of cynosure,
and the phoenix or unique fire-bird is a favorite poetic emblem, especially, in
England, for Queen Elizabeth. Garden symbolism recedes into the back ground, as
city symbolism does in romance; there are formal gardens in close association
with buildings, but the idea of a garden world is still a romantic one. The
magician's wand is metamorphosed into the royal sceptre, and the magic tree to
the fluttering banner. The city is preeminently the capital city, with the
court [153] at its center and a series of initiatory degrees of approach within
the court, climaxed by the royal "presence." We note that as we go
down the modes an increasing number of poetic images are taken from actual
social conditions of life. Water-symbolism centers on the disciplined river, in
England the Thames which runs softly in Spenser and in neo-Classical rhythms in
Denham, a river whose most appropriate ornament is the royal barge.
In the low mimetic area we enter a world that we may call the analogy
of experience, and which bears a relation to the demonic world
corresponding to the relation of the romantic innocent world to the apocalyptic
one. Except for this potentially ironic connection, and except for a certain
number of hieratic or specially indicated symbols like Hawthorne's scarlet
letter and Henry James's golden bowl and ivory tower, the images are the
ordinary images of experience, and need no further explanation here beyond a
few comments about some particular features that may be of use. The organizing
low mimetic ideas seem to be genesis and work. Divine and spiritual beings have
little functional place in low mimetic fiction, and in thematic writing they
are often deliberately rediscovered or treated as aesthetic surrogates. The
advice is given to the unborn in Erewhon (apparently close to
Butler's own view, as he repeats the idea in Life and Habit) that
if there is a spiritual world, one should turn one's back on it and find it
again in immediate work. The same doctrine of the rediscovery of faith through
works may be found in Carlyle, Ruskin, Morris, and Shaw. In poets, even in
explicitly sacramental ones, there are parallel tendencies. From many points of
view there could hardly be a greater contrast than the contrast between the
"motion and a spirit" discovered by Wordsworth in Tintern Abbey and
the "chevalier" discovered by Hopkins in the windhover, yet the
tendency to anchor a spiritual vision in an empirical psychological experience
is common to both.
The low mimetic treatment of human society reflects, of course,
Wordsworth's doctrine that the essential human situations, for the poet, are
the common and typical ones. Along with this goes a good deal of parody of the
idealization of life in romance, a parody that extends to religious and
aesthetic experience. As for the animal world, Thomas Huxley's reference to the
qualities that humanity shares with the ape and the tiger is a significantly
low mimetic choice. The ape has always been par excellence the mimetic [154]
animal, and long before evolution he was specifically the imitator of man. The
rise of evolution however suggested an analogy of proportion in which present
man becomes the ape of his counterpart in the future, as in Nietzsche's Zarathustra. Huxley's coupling of the ape and the tiger recalls the popular belief
in the implacable and invariable ferocity of both apes and "cavemen,"
a belief for which there seems to be little more evidence than for unicorns and
phoenixes, but which, like them, shows a tendency to look at natural history
from within the appropriate framework of poetic metaphors. The low mimetic is
not a rich field for animal symbolism, but Huxley's ape and tiger recur in
Kipling's Jungle Book, where the monkeys chatter in the
tree-tops to no purpose, like intellectuals, while the human animal learns
instead the dark predatory wisdom of the panther in the jungle below.
Gardens in the low mimetic give place to farms and the painful labor of
the man with the hoe, the peasant or furze cutter who stands in Hardy as an
image of man himself, "slighted and enduring." Cities take of course
the shape of the labyrinthine modern metropolis, where the main emotional
stress is on loneliness and lack of communication. And just as water symbolism in
the world of innocence consists largely of fountains and running streams, so
low mimetic imagery seeks Conrad's "destructive element" the sea,
generally with some humanized leviathan or bateau ivre on it of any size from the Titanic in Hardy to the capsizable open
boat which is, with an irony rare even in literature, a favorite image of
Shelley. Moby Dick returns us to a more
traditional form of the leviathan. The destroyer which appears at the end of H.
G. Wells's Tono-Bungay is notable as coming from a
low mimetic writer not much given to introducing hieratic symbols. Fire
symbolism is often ironic and destructive, as in the fire which ends the action
of The Spoils of Poynton. In the industrial age, however,
Prometheus, who stole fire for man's use, is one of the favorite, if not the
actual favorite, mythological figure among poets.
The relation of innocence and experience to apocalyptic and demonic
imagery illustrates an aspect of displacement which we have so far said little
about: displacement in the direction of the moral The two dialectical
structures are, radically, the desirable and the undesirable. Racks and
dungeons belong in the sinister vision not because they are morally forbidden
but because it is impossible [155] to make them objects of desire. Sexual
fulfilment, on the other hand, may be desired even if it is morally condemned.
Civilization tends to try to make the desirable and the moral coincide. The
student of comparative mythology occasionally turns up, in a primitive or
ancient cult, a bit of uninhibited mythopoeia that makes him realize how
completely all the higher religions have limited their apocalyptic visions to
morally acceptable ones. A good deal of expurgation clearly lies behind the
development of Jewish, Greek, and other mythologies; or, as Victorian students
of myth used to say, a repulsive and grotesque barbarism has been purified by a
growing ethical refinement. Egyptian mythology begins with a god who creates
the world by masturbation - a logical enough way of symbolizing the process of
creation de Deo but not one that we should
expect to find in Homer, to say nothing of the Old Testament. As long as poetry
follows religion towards the moral, religious and poetic archetypes will be
very close together, as they are in Dante. Under such influence apocalyptic
sexual imagery, for instance, tends to become matrimonial or virginal; the
incestuous, the homosexual, and the adulterous go on the demonic side. The
quality in art that Aristotle called spoudaios and that Matthew Arnold
translated as "high seriousness" results from this rapprochement of
religion and poetry within a common moral framework.
But poetry continually tends to right its own balance, to return to the
pattern of desire and away from the conventional and moral. It usually does
this in satire, the genre which is furthest removed from "high seriousness,"
but not always. The moral and the desirable have many important and significant
connections, but still morality, which comes to terms with experience and
necessity, is one thing, and desire, which tries to escape from necessity, is
quite another. Thus literature is as a rule less inflexible than morality, and
it owes much of its status as a liberal art to that fact. The qualities that
morality and religion usually call ribald, obscene, subversive, lewd, and
blasphemous have an essential place in literature, but often they can achieve
expression only through ingenious techniques of displacement.
The simplest of such techniques is the phenomenon that we may call
"demonic modulation," or the deliberate reversal of the customary
moral associations of archetypes. Any symbol at all takes its meaning primarily
from its context: a dragon may be sinister in a medieval romance or friendly in
a Chinese one; an island may be [156] Prospero's island or Circe's. But because
of the large amount of learned and traditional symbolism in literature, certain
secondary associations become habitual. The serpent, because of its role in the
garden of Eden story, usually belongs on the sinister side of our catalogue in
Western literature; the revolutionary sympathies of Shelley impel him to use an
innocent serpent in The Revolt of Islam. Or a free and equal society may
be symbolized by a band of robbers, pirates, or gypsies; or true love may be
symbolized by the triumph of an adulterous liaison over marriage, as in most
triangle comedy; by a homosexual passion (if it is true love that is celebrated
in Virgil's second eclogue) or an incestuous one, as in many Romantics. In the
nineteenth century, with demonic myth approaching, this kind of reversed
symbolism is organized into all the patterns of the "Romantic agony,"
chiefly sadism, Prometheanism, and diabolism, which in some of the
"decadents" seem to provide all the disadvantages of superstition
with none of the advantages of religion. Diabolism is not however invariably a
sophisticated development: Huckleberry Finn, for example, wins our sympathy and
admiration by preferring hell with his hunted friend to the heaven of the white
slave-owners' god. On the other hand, imagery traditionally demonic may be used
for the starting-point of a movement of redemption, like the City of
Destruction in The Pilgrims Progress. Alchemical symbolism takes the
ouroboros and the hermaphrodite (res
bina), as well as the
traditional romantic dragon, in this redemptive context.
Apocalyptic symbolism presents the infinitely desirable, in which the
lusts and ambitions of man are identified with, adapted to, or projected on the
gods. The art of the analogy of innocence, which includes most of the comic (in
its happy-ending aspect), the idyllic, the romantic, the reverent, the
panegyrical, the idealized, and the magical, is largely concerned with an
attempt to present the desirable in human, familiar, attainable, and morally
allowable terms. Much the same is true of the relation of the demonic world to
the analogy of experience. Tragedy, for instance, is a vision of what does
happen and must be accepted. To this extent it is a moral and plausible
displacement of the bitter resentments that humanity feels against all
obstacles to its desires. However malignant we may feel Athene to be in
Sophocles' Ajax, the tragedy clearly implies that we must come to terms with her
possession of power, even in our thoughts. A Christian who believed the Greek
[157] gods to be nothing but devils would, if he were criticizing a tragedy of
Sophocles, make an undisplaced or demonic interpretation of it. Such an
interpretation would bring out everything that Sophocles was trying not to say; but it could be a shrewd criticism of its latent or
underlying demonic structure for all that. The same kind of interpretation
would be equally possible for many passages of Christian poetry dealing with
the just wrath of God, the demonic content of which is often a hated
father-figure. In pointing out the latent apocalyptic or demonic patterns in a
literary work, we should not make the error of assuming that this latent
content is the red content hypocritically disguised by a lying censor. It is
simply one factor which is relevant to a full critical analysis. It is often,
however, the factor which lifts a work of literature out of the category of the
merely historical.
Theory
of Mythos: Introduction
The meaning of a poem, its structure of imagery, is a static pattern.
The five structures of meaning we have given are, to use an other musical analogy,
the keys in which they are written and finally resolve; but narrative involves
movement from one structure to another. The main area of such movement
obviously has to be the three intermediate fields. The apocalyptic and demonic
worlds, being structures of pure metaphorical identity, suggest the eternally
unchanging, and lend themselves very readily to being projected existentially
as heaven and hell, where there is continuous life but no process of life. The
analogies of innocence and experience represent the adaptation of myth to
nature: they give us, not the city and the garden at the final goal of human
vision, but the process of building and planting. The fundamental form of
process is cyclical movement, the alternation of success and decline, effort
and repose, life and death which is the rhythm of process. Hence our seven
categories of images may also be seen as different forms of rotary or cyclical
movement. Thus:
1. In the divine world the central process or movement is that of the
death and rebirth, or the disappearance and return, or the incarnation and
withdrawal, of a god. This divine activity is usually identified or associated
with one or more of the cyclical processes of nature. The god may be a sun-god,
dying at night and reborn at dawn, or else with an annual rebirth at the winter
solstice; or he [158] may be a god of vegetation, dying in autumn and reviving
in spring, or (as in the birth stones of the Buddha) he may be an incarnate god
going through a series of human or animal life-cycles. As a god is almost by
definition immortal, it is a regular feature of all such myths that the dying
god is reborn as the same person. Hence the mythical or abstract structural
principle of the cycle is that the continuum of identity in the individual life
from birth to death is extended from death to rebirth. To this pattern of
identical recurrence, the death and revival of the same individual, all other
cyclical patterns are as a rule assimilated. The assimilation can be of course
much closer in Eastern culture, where the doctrine of reincarnation is
generally accepted, than in the West.
2. The fire-world of heavenly bodies presents us with three important
cyclical rhythms. Most obvious is the daily journey of the sun-god across the
sky, often thought of as guiding a boat or chariot, followed by a mysterious
passage through a dark underworld, some times conceived as the belly of a
devouring monster, back to the starting point. The solstitial cycle of the
solar year supplies an extension of the same symbolism, incorporated in our
Christmas literature. Here there is more emphasis on the theme of a newborn
light threatened by the powers of darkness. The lunar cycle has been on the
whole of less importance to Western poetry in historic times, whatever its
prehistoric role. But its crucial sequence of old moon, "interlunar
cave," and new moon may be the source, as it is clearly a close analogy,
of the three-day rhythm of death, disappearance, and resurrection which we have
in our Easter symbolism.
3. The human world is midway between the spiritual and the animal, and
reflects that duality in its cyclical rhythms. Closely parallel to the solar
cycle of light and darkness is the imaginative cycle of waking and of dreaming
life. This cycle underlies the antithesis of the imagination of experience and
of innocence already dealt with. For the human rhythm is the opposite of the
solar one: a titanic libido wakes when the sun sleeps, and the light of day is
often the darkness of desire. Then again, in common with animals, man exhibits
the ordinary cycle of life and death, in which there is generic but not
individual rebirth.
4. It is rare, in literature as in life, to find even a domesticated
animal peacefully living through its full span of life to reach a final nunc dimittis. The exceptions, such as Odysseus' dog, are appropriate to the theme
of nostos or full close of a cyclical
movement. [159] Animal lives, and human lives similarly subject to the order of
nature suggest more frequently the tragic process of life cut off violently by
accident, sacrifice, ferocity, or some overriding need, the continuity which
flows on after the tragic act being something other than the life itself.
5. The vegetable world supplies us of course with the annual cycle of
seasons, often identified with or represented by a divine figure which dies in
the autumn or is killed with the gathering of the harvest and the vintage,
disappears in winter, and revives in spring. The divine figure may be male
(Adonis) or female (Proserpine), but the symbolic structures resulting differ
somewhat.
6. Poets, like critics, have generally been Spenglerians, in the sense
that in poetry, as in Spengler, civilized life is frequently assimilated to the
organic cycle of growth, maturity, decline, death, and rebirth in another
individual form. Themes of a golden or heroic age in the past, of a millennium
in the future, of the wheel of fortune in social affairs, of the ubi sunt elegy, of meditations over ruins, of nostalgia for a lost pastoral
simplicity, of regret or exultation over the collapse of an empire, belong
here.
7. Water-symbolism has also its own cycle, from rains to springs, from
springs and fountains to brooks and rivers, from rivers to the sea or the
winter snow, and back again.
These cyclical symbols are usually divided into four main phases, the
four seasons of the year being the type for four periods of the day (morning,
noon, evening, night), four aspects of the water-cycle (rain, fountains,
rivers, sea or snow), four periods of life (youth, maturity, age, death), and
the like. We find a great number of symbols from phases one and two in
Keats's Endymion, and of symbols from phases three
and four in The Waste Land (where we have to add four
stages of Western culture, medieval, Renaissance, eighteenth-century, and
contemporary). We may note that there is no cycle of air: the wind bloweth
where it listeth, and images dealing with the movement of "spirit"
are likely to be associated with the theme of unpredictability or sudden crisis.
In studying poems of immense scope, such as the Commedia or Paradise
Lost, we find that we have to learn a good deal of cosmology. This
cosmology is presented, quite correctly of course, as the science of its day, a
schematism of correspondences which, after supplying us with a not too
efficient calendar and a few words like [160] "phlegmatic" and
"jovial," became defunct as science. There are also other poems
incorporating equally obsolete science, such as The Purple Island, The
Loves of the Plants, The Art of Preserving Health, which
survive chiefly as curiosities. A literary critic should not overlook the
compliment to poetry implied by the existence of such poems, but still
versified science, as such, keeps the descriptive structure of science, and so
imposes a non-poetic form on poetry. To make it successful as poetry a great
deal of tact is required, yet those most attracted to such themes are very apt
to be tactless poets. Dante and Milton were certainly better poets than Darwin
or Fletcher: perhaps, however, it would be more fruitful to say that it was
their finer instincts and judgements that led them to cosmological, as distinct
from scientific or descriptive, themes.
For the form of cosmology is clearly much closer to that of poetry, and
the thought suggests itself that symmetrical cosmology may be a branch of myth.
If so, then it would be, like myth, a structural principle of poetry, whereas
in science itself, symmetrical cosmology is exactly what Bacon said it was, an
idol of the theatre. Perhaps, then, this whole pseudo-scientific world of three
spirits, four humors, five elements, seven planets, nine spheres, twelve
zodiacal signs, and so on, belongs in fact, as it does in practice, to the
grammar of literary imagery. It has long been noticed that the Ptolemaic
universe provides a better framework of symbolism, with all the identities,
associations, and correspondences that symbolism demands, than the Copernican
one does. Perhaps it not only provides a framework of poetic symbols but is
one, or at any rate becomes one after it loses its validity as science, just as
Classical mythology became purely poetic after its oracles had ceased. The same
principle would account for the attraction of poets in the last century or two
to occult systems of correspondences, and to such constructs as Yeats's Vision and Poe's Eureka.
The conception of a heaven above, a hell beneath, and a cyclical cosmos
or order of nature in between forms the ground plan, mutatis mutandis,
of both Dante and Milton. The same plan is in paintings of the Last Judgement,
where there is a rotary movement of the saved rising on the right and the
damned falling on the left. We may apply this construct to our principle that
there are two fundamental movements of narrative: a cyclical movement within
the order of nature, and a dialectical movement from that order [161] into the
apocalyptic world above. (The movement to the demonic world below is very rare,
because a constant rotation within the order of nature is demonic in itself.)
The top half of the natural cycle is the world of romance and the
analogy of innocence; the lower half is the world of "realism" and
the analogy of experience. There are thus four main types of mythical movement:
within romance, within experience, down, and up. The downward movement is the
tragic movement, the wheel of fortune falling from innocence toward hamartia,
and from hamartia to catastrophe. The upward movement is the comic movement,
from threatening complications to a happy ending and a general assumption of
post-dated innocence in which everyone lives happily ever after. In Dante the
upward movement is through purgatory.
We have thus answered the question: are there narrative categories of
literature broader than, or logically prior to, the ordinary literary genres?
There are four such categories: the romantic, the tragic, the comic, and the
ironic or satiric. We get the same answer by inspection if we look at the
ordinary meanings of these terms. Tragedy and comedy may have been originally
names for two species of drama, but we also employ the terms to describe
general characteristics of literary fictions, without regard to genre. It would
be silly to insist that comedy can refer only to a certain type of stage play,
and must never be employed in connection with Chaucer or Jane Austen. Chaucer
himself would certainly have defined comedy, as his monk defines tragedy, much
more broadly than that. If we are told that what we are about to read is tragic
or comic, we expect a certain kind of structure and mood, but not necessarily a
certain genre. The same is true of the word romance, and also of the words
irony and satire, which are, as generally employed, elements of the literature
of experience, and which we shall here adopt in place of "realism."
We thus have four narrative pregeneric elements of literature which I shall
call mythoi or generic plots.
If we think of our experience of these mythoi, we shall
realize that they form two opposed pairs. Tragedy and comedy contrast rather
than blend, and so do romance and irony, the champions respectively of the
ideal and the actual. On the other hand, comedy blends insensibly into satire
at one extreme and into romance at the other; romance may be comic or tragic;
tragic extends from high romance to bitter and ironic realism. [162]
Dramatic comedy, from which
fictional comedy is mainly descended, has been remarkably tenacious of its
structural principles and character types. Bernard Shaw remarked that a comic
dramatist could get a reputation for daring originality by stealing his method
from Moliere and his characters from Dickens: if we were to read Menander and
Aristophanes for Moliere and Dickens the statement would be hardly less true,
at least as a general principle. The earliest extant European comedy,
Aristophanes' The Acharnians, contains the miles gloriosus or
military braggart who is still going strong in Chaplin's Great Dictator;
the Joxer Daly of O 'Casey's Juno and the Paycock has the same
character and dramatic function as the parasites of twenty-five hundred years
ago, and the audiences of vaudeville, comic strips, and television programs
still laugh at the jokes that were declared to be outworn at the opening
of The Frogs.
The plot structure of Greek New Comedy, as transmitted by Plautus and
Terence, in itself less a form than a formula, has become the basis for most
comedy, especially in its more highly conventionalized dramatic form, down to
our own day. It will be most convenient to work out the theory of comic
construction from drama, using illustrations from fiction only incidentally.
What normally happens is that a young man wants a young woman, that his desire
is resisted by some opposition, usually paternal, and that near the end of the
play some twist in the plot enables the hero to have his will. In this simple
pattern there are several complex elements. In the first place, the movement of
comedy is usually a movement from one kind of society to another. At the
beginning of the play the obstructing characters are in charge of the play's
society, and the audience recognizes that they are usurpers. At the end of the
play the device in the plot that brings hero and heroine together causes a new
society to crystallize around the hero, and the moment when this
crystallization occurs is the point of resolution in the action, the comic
discovery, anagnorisis or cognitio.
The appearance of this new society is frequently signalized by some kind
of party or festive ritual, which either appears at the end of the play or is
assumed to take place immediately afterward. Weddings are most common, and
sometimes so many of them occur, as in the quadruple wedding at the end
of As You Like It, that they [163] suggest also the wholesale
pairing off that takes place in a dance, which is another common conclusion,
and the normal one for the masque. The banquet at the end of The Taming
of the Shrew has an ancestry that goes back to Greek Middle Comedy; in
Plautus the audience is sometimes jocosely invited to an imaginary banquet
afterwards; Old Comedy, like the modern Christmas pantomime, was more generous,
and occasionally threw bits of food to the audience. As the final society
reached by comedy is the one that the audience has recognized all along to be
the proper and desirable state of affairs, an act of communion with the
audience is in order. Tragic actors expect to be applauded as well as comic
ones, but nevertheless the word "plaudite" at the end of a Roman
comedy, the invitation to the audience to form part of the comic society, would
seem rather out of place at the end of a tragedy. The resolution of comedy
comes, so to speak, from the audience's side of the stage; in a tragedy it
comes from some mysterious world on the opposite side. In the movie, where
darkness permits a more erotically oriented audience, the plot usually moves
toward an act which, like death in Greek tragedy, takes place offstage, and is
symbolized by a closing embrace.
The obstacles to the hero's desire, then, form the action of the comedy,
and the overcoming of them the comic resolution. The obstacles are usually
parental, hence comedy often turns on a clash between a son's and a father's
will. Thus the comic dramatist as a rule writes for the younger men in his
audience, and the older members of almost any society are apt to feel that
comedy has something subversive about it. This is certainly one element in the
social persecution of drama, which is not peculiar to Puritans or even
Christians, as Terence in pagan Rome met much the same kind of social
opposition that Ben Jonson did. There is one scene in Plautus where a son and
father are making love to the same courtesan, and the son asks his father
pointedly if he really does love mother. One has to see this scene against the
background of Roman family life to understand its importance as psychological
release. Even in Shakespeare there are startling outbreaks of baiting older
men, and in contemporary movies the triumph of youth is so relentless that the
moviemakers find some difficulty in getting anyone over the age of seventeen
into their audiences.
The opponent to the hero's wishes, when not the father, is generally
someone who partakes of the father's closer relation to [164] established society:
that is, a rival with less youth and more money. In Plautus and Terence he is
usually either the pimp who owns the girl, or a wandering soldier with a supply
of ready cash. The fury with which these characters are baited and exploded
from the stage shows that they are father-surrogates, and even if they were
not, they would still be usurpers, and their claim to possess the girl must be
shown up as somehow fraudulent. They are, in short, impostors, and the extent
to which they have real power implies some criticism of the society that allows
them their power. In Plautus and Terence this criticism seldom goes beyond the
immorality of brothels and professional harlots, but in Renaissance dramatists,
including Jonson, there is some sharp observation of the rising power of money
and the sort of ruling class it is building up.
The tendency of comedy is to include as many people as possible in its
final society: the blocking characters are more often reconciled or converted
than simply repudiated. Comedy often includes a scapegoat ritual of expulsion
which gets rid of some irreconcilable character, but exposure and disgrace make
for pathos, or even tragedy. The Merchant of Venice seems
almost an experiment in coming as close as possible to upsetting the comic balance.
If the dramatic role of Shylock is ever so slightly exaggerated, as it
generally is when the leading actor of the company takes the part, it is upset,
and the play becomes the tragedy of the Jew of Venice with a comic
epilogue. Volpone ends with a great bustle of sentences to
penal servitude and the galleys, and one feels that the deliverance of society
hardly needs so much hard labor; but thenVolpone is exceptional in
being a kind of comic imitation of a tragedy, with the point of Volpone's
hubris carefully marked.
The principle of conversion becomes clearer with characters whose chief
function is the amusing of the audience. The original miles gloriosus in
Plautus is a son of Jove and Venus who has killed an elephant with his fist and
seven thousand men in one day's fighting. In other words, he is trying to put
on a good show: the exuberance of his boasting helps to put the play over. The
convention says that the braggart must be exposed, ridiculed, swindled, and
beaten. But why should a professional dramatist, of all people, want so to
harry a character who is putting on a good show - his show at that? When we
find Falstaff invited to the final feast in The Merry Wives,
Caliban reprieved, attempts made to mollify Malvolio, and Angelo and Parolles allowed
to live down their [165] disgrace, we are seeing a fundamental principle of
comedy at work. The tendency of the comic society to include rather than
exclude is the reason for the traditional importance of the parasite, who has
no business to be at the final festival but is nevertheless there. The word
"grace," with all its Renaissance overtones from the graceful
courtier of Castiglione to the gracious God of Christianity, is a most
important thematic word in Shakespearean comedy.
The action of comedy in moving from one social center to another is not
unlike the action of a lawsuit, in which plaintiff and defendant construct
different versions of the same situation, one finally being judged as real and
the other as illusory. This resemblance of the rhetoric of comedy to the
rhetoric of jurisprudence has been recognized from earliest times. A little
pamphlet called the Tractatus Coislinianus, closely related to
Aristotle's Poetics, which sets down all the essential facts about
comedy in about a page and a half, divides the dianoia of
comedy into two parts, opinion (pistis) and proof (gnosis). These
correspond roughly to the usurping and the desirable societies respectively.
Proofs (i.e., the means of bringing about the happier society) are subdivided
into oaths, compacts, witnesses, ordeals (or tortures), and laws in other words
the five forms of material proof in law cases listed in the Rhetoric. We notice
how often the action of a Shakespearean comedy begins with some absurd, cruel,
or irrational law: the law of killing Syracusans in the Comedy of
Errors, the law of compulsory marriage in A Midsummer Night's Dream,
the law that confirms Shylock's bond, the attempts of Angelo to legislate
people into righteousness, and the like, which the action of the comedy then
evades or breaks. Compacts are as a rule the conspiracies formed by the hero's
society; witnesses, such as overhearers of conversations or people with special
knowledge (like the hero's old nurse with her retentive memory for birthmarks),
are the commonest devices for bringing about the comic discovery. Ordeals (basanoi)
are usually tests or touchstones of the hero's character: the Greek word also
means touchstones, and seems to be echoed in Shakespeare's Bassanio whose
ordeal it is to make a judgement on the worth of metals.
There are two ways of developing the form of comedy: one is to throw the
main emphasis on the blocking characters; the other is to throw it forward on
the scenes of discovery and reconciliation. One is the general tendency of
comic irony, satire, realism, and [166] studies of manners; the other is the
tendency of Shakespearean and other types of romantic comedy. In the comedy of
manners the main ethical interest falls as a rule on the blocking characters.
The technical hero and heroine are not often very interesting people: the adulescentes of
Plautus and Terence are all alike, as hard to tell apart in the dark as
Demetrius and Lysander, who may be parodies of them. Generally the hero's
character has the neutrality that enables him to represent a wish-fulfilment.
It is very different with the miserly or ferocious parent, the boastful or
foppish rival, or the other characters who stand in the way of the action. In
Moliere we have a simple but fully tested formula in which the ethical interest
is focussed on a single blocking character, a heavy father, a miser, a
misanthrope, a hypocrite, or a hypochondriac. These are the figures that we
remember, and the plays are usually named after them, but we can seldom
remember all the Valentins and Angeliques who wriggle out of their clutches.
In The Merry Wives the technical hero, a man named Fenton, has
only a bit part, and this play has picked up a hint or two from Plautus's Casina,
where the hero and heroine are not even brought on the stage at all. Fictional
comedy, especially Dickens, often follows the same practice of grouping its
interesting characters around a somewhat dullish pair of technical leads. Even
Tom Jones, though far more fully realized, is still deliberately associated, as
his commonplace name indicates, with the conventional and typical.
Comedy usually moves toward a happy ending, and the normal response of
the audience to a happy ending is "this should be," which sounds like
a moral judgement. So it is, except that it is not moral in the restricted
sense, but social. Its opposite is not the villainous but the absurd, and
comedy finds the virtues of Malvolio as absurd as the vices of Angelo.
Moliere's misanthrope, being committed to sincerity, which is a virtue, is morally
in a strong position, but the audience soon realizes that his friend Philinte,
who is ready to lie quite cheerfully in order to enable other people to
preserve their self-respect, is the more genuinely sincere of the two. It is of
course quite possible to have a moral comedy, but the result is often the kind
of melodrama that we have described as comedy without humor, and which achieves
its happy ending with a self-righteous tone that most comedy avoids. It is
hardly possible to imagine a drama without conflict, and it is hardly possible
to imagine a conflict without some kind of enmity. But just as love, [167]
including sexual love, is a very different thing from lust, so enmity is a very
different thing from hatred. In tragedy, of course, enmity almost always
includes hatred; comedy is different, and one feels that the social judgement
against the absurd is closer to the comic norm than the moral judgement against
the wicked.
The question then arises of what makes the blocking character absurd.
Ben Jonson explained this by his theory of the "humor," the character
dominated by what Pope calls a ruling passion. The humor's dramatic function is
to express a state of what might be called ritual bondage. He is obsessed by
his humor, and his function in the play is primarily to repeat his obsession. A
sick man is not a humor, but a hypochondriac is, because, qua hypochondriac, he
can never admit to good health, and can never do anything inconsistent with the
role that he has prescribed for himself. A miser can do and say nothing that is
not connected with the hiding of gold or saving of money. In The Silent
Woman, Jonson's nearest approach to Moliere's type of construction, the
whole action recedes from the humor of Morose, whose determination to eliminate
noise from his life produces so loquacious a comic action.
The principle of the humor is the principle that unincremental
repetition, the literary imitation of ritual bondage, is funny. In a tragedy -Oedipus
Tyrannus is the stock example - repetition leads logically to
catastrophe. Repetition overdone or not going anywhere belongs to comedy, for
laughter is partly a reflex, and like other reflexes it can be conditioned by a
simple repeated pattern. In Synge's Riders to the Sea a
mother, after losing her husband and five sons at sea, finally loses her last
son, and the result is a very beautiful and moving play. But if it had been a
full-length tragedy plodding glumly through the seven drownings one after
another, the audience would have been helpless with unsympathetic laughter long
before it was over. The principle of repetition as the basis of humor both in
Jonson's sense and in ours is well known to the creators of comic strips, in
which a character is established as a parasite, a glutton (often confined to
one dish), or a shrew, and who begins to be funny after the point has been made
every day for several months. Continuous comic radio programs, too, are much
more amusing to habitues than to neophytes. The girth of Falstaff and the
hallucinations of Quixote are based on much the same comic laws. Mr. E. M.
Forster speaks with disdain of Dickens's Mrs. Micawber, who never says anything
except that she will never [168] desert Mr. Micawber: a strong contrast is
marked here between the refined writer too finicky for popular formulas, and
the major one who exploits them ruthlessly.
The humor in comedy is usually someone with a good deal of social
prestige and power, who is able to force much of the play's society into line
with his obsession. Thus the humor is intimately connected with the theme of
the absurd or irrational law that the action of comedy moves toward breaking.
It is significant that the central character of our earliest humor
comedy, The Wasps, is obsessed by law cases: Shylock, too, unites a
craving for the law with the humor of revenge. Often the absurd law appears as
a whim of a bemused tyrant whose will is law, like Leontes or the humorous Duke
Frederick in Shakespeare, who makes some arbitrary decision or rash promise:
here law is replaced by "oath," also mentioned in the Tractatus.
Or it may take the form of a sham Utopia, a society of ritual bondage
constructed by an act of humorous or pedantic will, like the academic retreat
in Love's Labor's Lost, This theme is also as old as Aristophanes,
whose parodies of Platonic social schemes in The Birds and Ecclesiazusae deal
with it.
The society emerging at the conclusion of comedy represents, by
contrast, a kind of moral norm, or pragmatically free society. Its ideals are
seldom defined or formulated: definition and formulation belong to the humors,
who want predictable activity. We are simply given to understand that the
newly-married couple will live happily ever after, or that at any rate they
will get along in a relatively unhumorous and clear-sighted manner. That is one
reason why the character of the successful hero is so often left undeveloped:
his real life begins at the end of the play, and we have to believe him to be
potentially a more interesting character than he appears to be. In Terence's Adelphoi,
Demea, a harsh father, is contrasted with his brother Micio, who is indulgent.
Micio being more liberal, he leads the way to the comic resolution, and
converts Demea, but then Demea points out the indolence inspiring a good deal
of Micio's liberality, and releases him from a complementary humorous bondage.
Thus the movement from pistis to gnosis,
from a society controlled by habit, ritual bondage, arbitrary law and the older
characters to a society controlled by youth and pragmatic freedom is
fundamentally, as the Greek words suggest, a movement from illusion to reality.
Illusion is whatever is fixed or definable, and reality [169] is best
understood as its negation: whatever reality is, it's not that.
Hence the importance of the theme of creating and dispelling illusion in
comedy: the illusions caused by disguise, obsession, hypocrisy, or unknown
parentage.
The comic ending is generally manipulated by a twist in the plot. In
Roman comedy the heroine, who is usually a slave or courtesan, turns out to be
the daughter of somebody respectable, so that the hero can marry her without
loss of face. The cognitio in comedy, in which the characters
find out who their relatives are, and who is left of the opposite sex not a
relative, and hence available for marriage, is one of the features of comedy
that have never changed much: The Confidential Clerk indicates
that it still holds the attention of dramatists. There is a brilliant parody of
a cognitio at the end of Major Barbara (the
fact that the hero of this play is a professor of Greek perhaps indicates an
unusual affinity to the conventions of Euripides and Menander), where
Undershaft is enabled to break the rule that he cannot appoint his son-in-law
as successor by the fact that the son-in-law's own father married his deceased
wife's sister in Australia, so that the son-in-law is his own first cousin as
well as himself. It sounds complicated, but the plots of comedy often are
complicated because there is something inherently absurd about complications.
As the main character interest in comedy is so often focussed on the defeated
characters, comedy regularly illustrates a victory of arbitrary plot over
consistency of character. Thus, in striking contrast to tragedy, there can
hardly be such a thing as inevitable comedy, as far as the action of the
individual play is concerned. That is, we may know that the convention of
comedy will make some kind of happy ending inevitable, but still for each play
the dramatist must produce a distinctive "gimmick" or "weenie,"
to use two disrespectful Hollywood synonyms for anagnorisis. Happy
endings do not impress us as true, but as desirable, and they are brought about
by manipulation. The watcher of death and tragedy has nothing to do but sit and
wait for the in evitable end; but something gets born at the end of comedy, and
the watcher of birth is a member of a busy society.
The manipulation of plot does not always involve metamorphosis of
character, but there is no violation of comic decorum when it does. Unlikely conversions,
miraculous transformations, and providential assistance are inseparable from
comedy. Further, whatever emerges is supposed to be there for good: if the
[170] curmudgeon becomes lovable, we understand that he will not immediately
relapse again into his ritual habit. Civilizations which stress the desirable
rather than the real, and the religious as opposed to the scientific
perspective, think of drama almost entirely in terms of comedy. In the
classical drama of India, we are told, the tragic ending was regarded as bad
taste, much as the manipulated endings of comedy are regarded as bad taste by
novelists interested in ironic realism.
The total mythos of comedy, only a small part of which
is ordinarily presented, has regularly what in music is called a ternary form:
the hero's society rebels against the society of the senex and
triumphs, but the hero's society is a Saturnalia, a reversal of social
standards which recalls a golden age in the past before the main action of the
play begins. Thus we have a stable and harmonious order disrupted by folly,
obsession, forgetfulness, "pride and prejudice," or events not
understood by the characters themselves, and then restored. Often there is a
benevolent grandfather, so to speak, who overrules the action set up by the
blocking humor and so links the first and third parts. An example is Mr.
Burchell, the disguised uncle of the wicked squire, in The Vicar of
Wakefteld. A very long play, such as the Indian Sakuntala, may
present all three phases; a very intricate one, such as many of Menander's
evidently were, may indicate their outlines. But of course very often the first
phase is not given at all: the audience simply understands an ideal state of
affairs which it knows to be better than what is revealed in the play, and
which it recognizes as like that to which the action leads. This ternary action
is, ritually, like a contest of summer and winter in which winter occupies the
middle action; psychologically, it is like the removal of a neurosis or
blocking point and the restoring of an unbroken current of energy and memory.
The Jonsonian masque, with the antimasque in the middle, gives a highly
conventionalized or "abstract" version of it.
We pass now to the typical characters of comedy. In drama, characterization
depends on function; what a character is follows from what he has to do in the
play. Dramatic function in its turn depends on the structure of the play; the
character has certain things to do because the play has such and such a shape.
The structure of the play in its turn depends on the category of the play; if
it is a comedy, its structure will require a comic resolution and a [171] prevailing comic mood. Hence when we speak of typical characters,
we are not trying to reduce lifelike characters to stock types, though we
certainly are suggesting that the sentimental notion of an antithesis between
the lifelike character and the stock type is a vulgar error. All lifelike
characters, whether in drama or fiction, owe their consistency to the
appropriateness of the stock type which belongs to their dramatic function.
That stock type is not the character but it is as necessary to the character as
a skeleton is to the actor who plays it.
With regard to the characterization of comedy, the Tractatus lists
three types of comic characters: the alazons or impostors,
the eirons or self-deprecators, and the buffoons (bomolochoi).
This list is closely related to a passage in the Ethics which
contrasts the first two, and then goes on to contrast the buffoon with a
character whom Aristotle calls agroikos or churlish, literally
rustic. We may reasonably accept the churl as a fourth character type, and so
we have two opposed pairs. The contest of eiron and alazon forms
the basis of the comic action, and the buffoon and the churl polarize the comic
mood.
We have previously dealt with the terms eiron and alazon.
The humorous blocking characters of comedy are nearly always impostors, though
it is more frequently a lack of self-knowledge than simple hypocrisy that characterizes
them. The multitudes of comic scenes in which one character complacently
soliloquizes while an other makes sarcastic asides to the audience show the
contest of eiron and alazon in its purest
form, and show too that the audience is sympathetic to the eiron side.
Central to the alazon group is the senex iratus or
heavy father, who with his rages and threats, his obsessions and his
gullibility, seems closely related to some of the demonic characters of
romance, such as Polyphemus. Occasionally a character may have the dramatic
function of such a figure with out his characteristics: an example is Squire
Allworthy in Tom Jones, who as far as the plot is concerned behaves
almost as stupidly as Squire Western. Of heavy-father surrogates, the miles
gloriosus has been mentioned: his popularity is largely due to the
fact that he is a man of words rather than deeds, and is consequently far more
useful to a practising dramatist than any tight-lipped hero could ever be. The
pedant, in Renaissance comedy often a student of the occult sciences, the fop
or coxcomb, and similar humors, require no comment. The female alazon is
rare: Katharina the [172] shrew represents to some extent a female miles
gloriosus, and the precieuse ridicule a female pedant, but
the "menace" or siren who gets in the way of the true heroine is more
often found as a sinister figure of melodrama or romance than as a ridiculous
figure in comedy.
The eiron figures need a little more attention. Central
to this group is the hero, who is an eiron figure because, as
explained, the dramatist tends to play him down and make him rather neutral and
unformed in character. Next in importance is the heroine, also often played
down: in Old Comedy, when a girl accompanies a male hero in his triumph, she is
generally a stage prop, a muta persona not previously
introduced. A more difficult form of cognitio is achieved when
the heroine disguises herself or through some other device brings about the
comic resolution, so that the person whom the hero is seeking turns out to be
the person who has sought him. The fondness of Shakespeare for this "she
stoops to conquer" theme needs only to be mentioned here, as it belongs
more naturally to the mythos of romance.
Another central eiron figure is the type entrusted with
hatching the schemes which bring about the hero's victory. This character in
Roman comedy is almost always a tricky slave (dolosus servus), and in
Renaissance comedy he becomes the scheming valet who is so frequent in
Continental plays, and in Spanish drama is called the gracioso.
Modern audiences are most familiar with him in Figaro and in the Leporello ofDon
Giovanni. Through such intermediate nineteenth-century figures as Micawber
and the Touchwood of Scott's St. Ronan's Well, who, like the
gracioso, have buffoon affiliations, he evolves into the amateur detective of
modern fiction. The Jeeves of P. G. Wodehouse is a more direct descendant.
Female confidantes of the same general family are often brought in to oil the
machinery of the well-made play. Elizabethan comedy had another type of
trickster, represented by the Matthew Merrygreek of Ralph Roister
Doister, who is generally said to be developed from the vice or iniquity of
the morality plays: as usual, the analogy is sound enough, whatever historians
decide about origins. The vice, to give him that name, is very useful to a
comic dramatist because he acts from pure love of mischief, and can set a comic
action going with the minimum of motivation. The vice may be as light-hearted
as Puck or as malignant as Don John in Much Ado, but as a rule the
vice's activity is, in spite of his name, benevolent [173] One of the tricky
slaves in Plautus, in a soliloquy, boasts that he is the architectus of
the comic action: such a character carries out the will of the author to reach
a happy ending. He is in fact the spirit of comedy, and the two clearest
examples of the type in Shakespeare, Puck and Ariel, are both spiritual beings.
The tricky slave often has his own freedom in mind as the reward of his
exertions: Ariel's longing for release is in the same tradition.
The role of the vice includes a great deal of disguising, and the type
may often be recognized by disguise. A good example is the Brainworm of
Jonson's Every Man in His Humour, who calls the action of the play
the day of his metamorphoses. Similarly Ariel has to surmount the difficult
stage direction of "Enter invisible." The vice is combined with the
hero whenever the latter is a cheeky, improvident young man who hatches his own
schemes and cheats his rich father or uncle into giving him his patrimony along
with the girl.
Another eiron type has not been much noticed. This is a
character, generally an older man, who begins the action of the play by
withdrawing from it, and ends the play by returning. He is often a father with
the motive of seeing what his son will do. The action of Every Man in
His Humour is set going in this way by Knowell Senior. The
disappearance and return of Lovewit, the owner of the house which is the scene
of The Alchemist, has the same dramatic function, though the
characterization is different. The clearest Shakespearean example is the Duke
in Measure for Measure, but Shakespeare is more addicted to the
type than might appear at first glance. In Shakespeare the vice is rarely the realarchitectus:
Puck and Ariel both act under orders from an older man, if one may call Oberon
a man for the moment. In The Tempest Shakespeare returns to a
comic action established by Aristophanes, in which an older man, instead of
retiring from the action, builds it up on the stage. When the heroine takes the
vice role in Shakespeare, she is often significantly related to her father,
even when the father is not in the play at all, like the father of Helena, who
gives her his medical knowledge, or the father of Portia, who arranges the
scheme of the caskets. A more conventionally treated example of the same
benevolent Prospero figure turned up recently in the psychiatrist of The
Cocktail Party, and one may compare the mysterious alchemist who is the
father of the heroine of The Lady's Not for Burning. The formula is
not confined to comedy: Polonius, who shows [174] so many of the disadvantages
of a literary education, attempts the role of a retreating paternal eiron three
times, once too often. Hamlet and King Lear contain subplots which are ironic
versions of stock comic themes, Gloucester's story being the regular comedy
theme of the gullible senex swindled by a clever and
unprincipled son.
We pass now to the buffoon types, those whose function it is to increase
the mood of festivity rather than to contribute to the plot. Renaissance
comedy, unlike Roman comedy, had a great variety of such characters,
professional fools, clowns, pages, singers, and incidental characters with
established comic habits like malapropism or foreign accents. The oldest
buffoon of this incidental nature is the parasite, who may be given something
to do, as Jonson gives Mosca the role of a vice in Volpone, but
who, qua parasite, does nothing but entertain the audience by
talking about his appetite. He derives chiefly from Greek Middle Comedy, which
appears to have been very full of food, and where he was, not unnaturally,
closely associated with another established buffoon type, the cook, a
conventional figure who breaks into comedies to bustle and order about and make
long speeches about the mysteries of cooking. In the role of cook the buffoon
or entertainer appears, not simply as a gratuitous addition like the parasite,
but as something more like a master of ceremonies, a center for the comic mood.
There is no cook in Shakespeare, though there is a superb description of one in
the Comedy of Errors, but a similar role is often attached to a
jovial and loquacious host, like the "mad host" of The Merry
Wives or the Simon Eyre of The Shoemakers Holiday. In
Middleton's A Trick to Catch the Old One the mad host type is
combined with the vice. In Falstaff and Sir Toby Belch we can see the
affinities of the buffoon or entertainer type both with the parasite and with
the master of revels. If we study this entertainer or host role carefully we
shall soon realize that it is a development of what in Aristophanic comedy is
represented by the chorus, and which in its turn goes back to the komos or
revel from which comedy is said to be descended.
Finally, there is a fourth group to which we have assigned the
word agroikos, and which usually means either churlish or rustic,
depending on the context. This type may also be extended to cover the
Elizabethan gull and what in vaudeville used to be called the straight man, the
solemn or inarticulate character who allows the [175] humor to bounce off him,
so to speak. We find churls in the miserly, snobbish, or priggish characters
whose role is that of the refuser of festivity, the killjoy who tries to stop
the fun, or, like Malvolio, locks up the food and drink instead of dispensing
it. The melancholy Jaques of As You Like It, who walks out on the
final festivities, is closely related. In the sulky and self-centered Bertram
of All's Well there is a most unusual and ingenious
combination of this type with the hero. More often, however, the churl belongs
to thealazon group, all miserly old men in comedies, including
Shylock, being churls. In The Tempest Caliban has much the
same relation to the churlish type that Ariel has to the vice or tricky slave.
But often, where the mood is more light-hearted, we may translate agroikos simply
by rustic, as with the innumerable country squires and similar characters who
provide amusement in the urban setting of drama. Such types do not refuse the
mood of festivity, but they mark the extent of its range. In a pastoral comedy
the idealized virtues of rural life may be represented by a simple man who
speaks for the pastoral ideal, like Corin in As You Like It Corin
has the same agroikos role as the "rube" or
"hayseed" of more citified comedies, but the moral attitude to the
role is reversed. Again we notice the principle that dramatic structure is a
permanent and moral attitude a variable factor in literature.
In a very ironic comedy a different type of character may play the role
of the refuser of festivity. The more ironic the comedy, the more absurd the
society, and an absurd society may be condemned by, or at least contrasted
with, a character that we may call the plain dealer, an outspoken advocate of a
kind of moral norm who has the sympathy of the audience. Wycherley's Manly,
though he provides the name for the type, is not a particularly good example of
it: a much better one is the Cleante of Tartuffe. Such a character
is appropriate when the tone is ironic enough to get the audience confused
about its sense of the social norm: he corresponds roughly to the chorus in a
tragedy, which is there for a similar reason. When the tone deepens from the
ironic to the bitter, the plain dealer may become a malcontent or railer, who
may be morally superior to his society, as he is to some extent in Marston's
play of that name, but who may also be too motivated by envy to be much more
than another aspect of his society's evil, like Thersites, or to some extent
Apemantus. [176]
In tragedy, pity and fear, the emotions of moral attraction and
repulsion, are raised and cast out. Comedy seems to make a more functional use
of the social, even the moral judgement, than tragedy, yet comedy seems to
raise the corresponding emotions, which are sympathy and ridicule, and cast
them out in the same way. Comedy ranges from the most savage irony to the most
dreamy wish-fulfilment romance, but its structural patterns and
characterization are much the same throughout its range. This principle of the
uniformity of comic structure through a variety of attitudes is clear in
Aristophanes. Aristophanes is the most personal of writers, and his opinions on
every subject are written all over his plays. We know that he wanted peace with
Sparta and that he hated Cleon, so when his comedy depicts the attaining of
peace and the defeat of Cleon we know that he approved and wanted his audience
to approve. But in Ecclesidzusae a band of women in disguise
railroad a communistic scheme through the Assembly which is a horrid parody of
a Platonic republic, and proceed to inaugurate its sexual communism with some
astonishing improvements. Presumably Aristophanes did not altogether endorse
this, yet the comedy follows the same pattern and the same resolution. InThe
Birds the Peisthetairos who defies Zeus and blocks out Olympus with
his Cloud-Cuckoo-Land is accorded the same triumph that is given to the
Trygaios of the Peace who flies to heaven and brings a golden
age back to Athens.
Let us look now at a variety of comic structures between the extremes of
irony and romance. As comedy blends into irony and satire at one end and into
romance at the other, if there are different phases or types of comic
structure, some of them will be closely parallel to some of the types of irony
and of romance. A somewhat forbidding piece of symmetry turns up in our
argument at this point, which seems to have some literary analogy to the circle
of fifths in music. I recognize six phases of each mythos, three
being parallel to the phases of a neighboring mythos. The first
three phases of comedy are parallel to the first three phases of irony and
satire, and the second three to the second three of romance. The distinction
between an ironic comedy and a comic satire, or between a romantic comedy and a
comic romance, is tenuous, but not quite a distinction without a difference.
The first or most ironic phase of comedy is, naturally, the one is which
a humorous society triumphs or remains undefeated. A good [177] example of a
comedy of this type is The Alchemist, in which the returning eiron Lovewit
joins the rascals, and the plain dealer Surly is made a fool of. In The
Beggar's Opera there is a similar twist to the ending: the (projected)
author feels that the hanging of the hero is a comic ending, but is informed by
the manager that the audience's sense of comic decorum demands a reprieve,
whatever Macheath's moral status. This phase of comedy presents what
Renaissance critics called speculum consuetudinis, the way of the
world, cosi fan tutte. A more intense irony is achieved when the
humorous society simply disintegrates without anything taking its place, as
in Heartbreak House and frequently in Chekhov.
We notice in ironic comedy that the demonic world is never far away. The
rages of the senex iratus in Roman comedy are directed mainly
at the tricky slave, who is threatened with the mill, with being flogged to
death, with crucifixion, with having his head dipped in tar and set on fire,
and the like, all penalties that could be and were exacted from slaves in life.
An epilogue in Plautus informs us that the slave-actor who has blown up in his
lines will now be flogged; in one of the Menander fragments a slave is tied up
and burned with a torch on the stage. One sometimes gets the impression that
the audience of Plautus and Terence would have guffawed uproariously all
through the Passion. We may ascribe this to the brutality of a slave society,
but then we remember that boiling oil and burying alive ("such a stuffy death")
turn up in The Mikado. Two lively comedies of the modern stage
are The Cocktail Party and The Lady's Not for Burning,
but the cross appears in the background of the one and the stake in the
background of the other. Shylock's knife and Angelo's gallows appear in
Shakespeare: in Measure for Measure every male character is at
one time or an other threatened with death. The action of comedy moves toward a
deliverance from something which, if absurd, is by no means invariably
harmless. We notice too how frequently a comic dramatist tries to bring his
action as close to a catastrophic overthrow of the hero as he can get it, and
then reverses the action as quickly as possible. The evading or breaking of a
cruel law is often a very narrow squeeze. The intervention of the king at the
end of Tartuffe is deliberately arbitrary: there is nothing in
the action of the play itself to prevent Tartuffe's triumph. Tom Jones in the
final book, accused of murder, incest, debt, and double-dealing, cast off by
friends, guardian, and sweetheart, is a woeful figure indeed before all these
turn into [178] illusions. Any reader can think of many comedies in which the
fear of death, sometimes a hideous death, hangs over the central character to
the end, and is dispelled so quickly that one has almost the sense of awakening
from nightmare.
Sometimes the redeeming agent actually is divine, like Diana in Pericles;
in Tartuffe it is the king, who is conceived as a part of the
audience and the incarnation of its will. An extraordinary number of comic
stories, both in drama and fiction, seem to approach a potentially tragic
crisis near the end, a feature that I may call the "point of ritual
death" a clumsy expression that I would gladly surrender for a better one.
It is a feature not often noticed by critics, but when it is present it is as
unmistakably present as a stretto in a fugue, which it somewhat resembles. In
Smollett'sHumphry Clinker (I select this because no one will
suspect Smollett of deliberate mythopoeia but only of following convention, at
least as far as his plot is concerned) , the main characters are nearly drowned
in an accident with an upset carriage; they are then taken to a nearby house to
dry off, and a cognitio takes place, in the course of which
their family relationships are regrouped, secrets of birth brought to light,
and names changed. Similar points of ritual death may be marked in almost any
story that imprisons the hero or gives the heroine a nearly mortal illness
before an eventually happy ending.
Sometimes the point of ritual death is vestigial, not an element in the
plot but a mere change of tone. Everyone will have noted in comic actions, even
in very trivial movies and magazine stories, a point near the end at which the
tone suddenly becomes serious, sentimental, or ominous of potential
catastrophe. In Aldous Huxley's Chrome Yellow, the hero Denis comes
to a point of self-evaluation in which suicide nearly suggests itself: in most
of Huxley's later books some violent action, generally suicidal, occurs at the
corresponding point. In Mrs. Dalloway the actual suicide of
Septimus becomes a point of ritual death for the heroine in the middle of her
party. There are also some interesting Shakespearean variations of the device:
a clown, for instance, will make a speech near the end in which the buffoon's
mask suddenly falls off and we look straight into the face of a beaten and
ridiculed slave. Examples are the speech of Dromio of Ephesus beginning "I
am an ass indeed" in the Comedy of Errors, and the speech of
the Clown in All's Well beginning "I am a woodland
fellow." [179]
The second phase of comedy, in its simplest form, is a comedy in which
the hero does not transform a humorous society but simply escapes or runs away
from it, leaving its structure as it was before. A more complex irony in this
phase is achieved when a society is constructed by or around a hero, but proves
not sufficiently real or strong to impose itself. In this situation the hero is
usually himself at least partly a comic humor or mental runaway, and we have
either a hero's illusion thwarted by a superior reality or a clash of two
illusions. This is the quixotic phase of comedy, a difficult phase for drama,
though The Wild Duck is a fairly pure example of it, and in
drama it usually appears as a subordinate theme of another phase. Thus in The
Alchemist Sir Epicure Mammon's dream of what he will do with the
philosopher's stone is, like Quixote's, a gigantic dream, and makes him an
ironic parody of Faustus (who is mentioned in the play), in the same way that
Quixote is an ironic parody of Amadis and Lancelot. When the tone is more
light-hearted, the comic resolution may be strong enough to sweep over all
quixotic illusions. In Huckleberry Finn the main theme is one
of the oldest in comedy, the freeing of a slave, and the cognitio tells
us that Jim had already been set free before his escape was bungled by Tom
Sawyer's pedantries. Because of its unrivalled opportunities for double-edged
irony, this phase is a favorite of Henry James: perhaps his most searching
study of it is The Sacred Fount, where the hero is an ironic parody
of a Prospero figure creating another society out of the one in front of him.
The third phase of comedy is the normal one that we have been
discussing, in which a senex iratus or other humor gives way
to a young man's desires. The sense of the comic norm is so strong that when
Shakespeare, by way of experiment, tried to reverse the pattern in All's
Well, in having two older people force Bertram to marry Helena, the result
has been an unpopular "problem" play, with a suggestion of something
sinister about it. We have noted that the cognitio of comedy
is much concerned with straightening out the details of the new society, with
distinguishing brides from sisters and parents from foster-parents. The fact
that the son and father are so often in conflict means that they are frequently
rivals for the same girl, and the psychological alliance of the hero's bride
and the mother is often expressed or implied. The occasional
"naughtiness" of comedy, as in the Restoration period, has much to
do, not only with marital infidelity, but with a kind of comic [180] Oedipus
situation in which the hero replaces his father as a lover. In Congreve's Love
for Love there are two Oedipus themes in counterpoint: the hero cheats
his father out of the heroine, and his best friend violates the wife of an
impotent old man who is the heroine's guardian. A theme which would be
recognized in real life as a form of infantile regression, the hero pretending
to be impotent in order to gain admission to the women's quarters, is employed
in Wycherley's Country Wife, where it is taken from Terence's Eunuchus.
The possibilities of incestuous combinations form one of the minor
themes of comedy. The repellent older woman offered to Figaro in marriage turns
out to be his mother, and the fear of violating a mother also occurs in Tom
Jones. When in Ghosts and Little Eyolf Ibsen
employed the old chestnut about the object of the hero's affections being his sister
(a theme as old as Menander), his startled hearers took it for a portent of
social revolution. In Shakespeare the recurring and somewhat mysterious
father-daughter relationship already alluded to appears in its incestuous form
at the beginning of Pericles, where it forms the demonic antithesis
of the hero's union with his wife and daughter at the end. The presiding genius
of comedy is Eros, and Eros has to adapt himself to the moral facts of society:
Oedipus and incest themes indicate that erotic attachments have in their
undisplaced or mythical origin a much greater versatility.
Ambivalent attitudes naturally result, and ambivalence is apparently the
main reason for the curious feature of doubled characters which runs all
through the history of comedy. In Roman comedy there is often a pair of young
men, and consequently a pair of young women, of which one is often related to
one of the men and exogamous to the other. The doubling of the senex figure
sometimes gives us a heavy father for both the hero and the heroine, as
in The Winter's Tale, sometimes a heavy father and benevolent
uncle, as in Terence's Adelphoi and in Tartuffe,
and so on. The action of comedy, like the action of the Christian Bible, moves
from law to liberty. In the law there is an element of ritual bondage which is
abolished, and an element of habit or convention which is fulfilled. The
intolerable qualities of the senex represent the former and
compromise with him the latter in the evolution of the comic nomos.
With the fourth phase of comedy we begin to move out of the [181] world
of experience into the ideal world of innocence and romance. We said that
normally the happier society established at the end of the comedy is left
undefined, in contrast to the ritual bondage of the humors. But it is also
possible for a comedy to present its action on two social planes, of which one
is preferred and consequently in some measure idealized. At the beginning of
Plato's Republic we have a sharp contest between the alazon Thrasymachus
and the ironic Socrates. The dialogue could have stopped there, as several of
Plato's dialogues do, with a negative victory over a humor and the kind of
society he suggests. But in the Republic the rest of the company, including
Thrasymachus, follow Socrates inside Socrates's head, so to speak, and
contemplate there the pattern of the just state. In Aristophanes the comic
action is often ironic, but in The Acharnians we have a comedy
in which a hero with the significant name of Dicaeopolis (righteous city or
citizen) makes a private peace with Sparta, celebrates the peaceful festival of
Dionysos with his family, and sets up the pattern of a temperate social order
on the stage, where it remains throughout the play, cranks, bigots, sharpers,
and scoundrels all being beaten away from it. One of the typical comic actions
is at least as clearly portrayed in our earliest comedy as it has ever been
since.
Shakespeare's type of romantic comedy follows a tradition established by
Peele and developed by Greene and Lyly, which has affinities with the medieval
tradition of the seasonal ritual-play. We may call it the drama of the green
world, its plot being assimilated to the ritual theme of the triumph of life
and love over the waste land. In The Two Gentlemen of Verona the
hero Valentine becomes captain of a band of outlaws in a forest, and all the
other characters are gathered into this forest and become converted. Thus the
action of the comedy begins in a world represented as a normal world, moves
into the green world, goes into a metamorphosis there in which the comic
resolution is achieved, and returns to the normal world. The forest in this
play is the embryonic form of the fairy world of A Midsummer Night's
Dream, the Forest of Arden in As You Like It, Windsor Forest
in The Merry Wives, and the pastoral world of the mythical
sea-coasted Bohemia in The Winter's Tale. In all these comedies
there is the same rhythmic movement from normal world to green world and back
again. In The Merchant of Venice the second world takes the
form of Portia's mysterious house in Belmont, with its magic caskets and the
wonderful [182] cosmological harmonies that proceed from it in the fifth act.
We notice too that this second world is absent from the more ironic
comedies All's Well and Measure for Measure.
The green world charges the comedies with the symbolism of the victory
of summer over winter, as is explicit in Love's Labor's Lost, where
the comic contest takes the form of the medieval debate of winter and spring at
the end. In The Merry Wives there is an elaborate ritual of
the defeat of winter known to folklorists as "carrying out Death," of
which Falstaff is the victim; and Falstaff must have felt that, after being
thrown into the water, dressed up as a witch and beaten out of a house with
curses, and finally supplied with a beast's head and singed with candles, he
had done about all that could reasonably be asked of any fertility spirit.
In the rituals and myths the earth that produces the rebirth is
generally a female figure, and the death and revival, or disappearance and
withdrawal, of human figures in romantic comedy generally involves the heroine.
The fact that the heroine often brings about the comic resolution by disguising
herself as a boy is familiar enough. The treatment of Hero in Much Ado,
of Helena in All's Well, of Thaisa in Pericles, of
Fidele in Cymbeline, of Hermione in The Winter's Tale,
show the repetition of a device in which progressively less care is taken of
plausibility and in which in consequence the mythical outline of a Proserpine
figure becomes progressively clearer. These are Shakespearean examples of the
comic theme of ritual assault on a central female figure, a theme which
stretches from Menander to contemporary soap operas. Many of Menander's plays
have titles which are feminine participles indicating the particular indignity
the heroine suffers in them, and the working formula of the soap opera is said
to be to "put the heroine behind the eight-ball and keep her there."
Treatments of the theme may be as light-hearted as The Rape of the Lock or
as doggedly persistent as Pamela. However, the theme of rebirth is
not invariably feminine in context: the rejuvenation of the senex in
Aristophanes' The Knights, and a similar theme in All's
Well based on the folklore motif of the healing of the impotent king,
come readily to mind.
The green world has analogies, not only to the fertile world of ritual,
but to the dream world that we create out of our own desires. This dream world
collides with the stumbling and blinded follies of the world of experience, of
Theseus' Athens with its [183] idiotic marriage law, of Duke Frederick and his
melancholy tyranny, of Leontes and his mad jealousy, of the Court Party with
their plots and intrigues, and yet proves strong enough to impose the form of
desire on it. Thus Shakespearean comedy illustrates, as clearly as any mythos
we have, the archetypal function of literature in visualizing the world of
desire, not as an escape from "reality," but as the genuine form of
the world that human life tries to imitate.
In the fifth phase of comedy, some of the themes of which we have
already anticipated, we move into a world that is still more romantic, less
Utopian and more Arcadian, less festive and more pensive, where the comic
ending is less a matter of the way the plot turns out than of the perspective
of the audience. When we compare the Shakespearean fourth-phase comedies with
the late fifth-phase "romances," we notice how much more serious an
action is appropriate to the latter: they do not avoid tragedies but contain
them. The action seems to be not only a movement from a "winter's
tale" to spring, but from a lower world of confusion to an upper world of
order. The closing scene of The Winter's Talemakes us think, not
simply of a cyclical movement from tragedy and absence to happiness and return,
but of bodily metamorphosis and a transformation from one kind of life to
another. The materials of the cognitio of Pericles or The
Winter's Tale are so stock that they would be "hooted at like an
old tale," yet they seem both far-fetched and inevitably right, outraging
reality and at the same time introducing us to a world of childlike innocence
which has always made more sense than reality.
In this phase the reader or audience feels raised above the action, in
the situation of which Christopher Sly is an ironic parody. The plotting of
Cleon and Dionyza in Pericles, or of the Court Party in The
Tempest, we look down on as generic or typical human behavior: the action,
or at least the tragic implication of the action, is presented as though it
were a play within a play that we can see in all dimensions at once. We see the
action, in short, from the point of view of a higher and better ordered world.
And as the forest in Shakespeare is the usual symbol for the dream world in
conflict with and imposing its form on experience, so the usual symbol for the
lower or chaotic world is the sea, from which the cast, or an important part of
it, is saved. The group of "sea" comedies includes A Comedy
of Errors, Twelfth Night, Pericles, and [184] The
Tempest. A Comedy of Errors, though based on a Plautine
original, is much closer to the world of Apuleius than to that of Plautus in
its imagery, and the main action, moving from shipwreck and separation to
reunion in a temple in Ephesus, is repeated in the much later play of Pericles.
And just as the second world is absent from the two "problem"
comedies, so in two of the "sea" group, Twelfth Night and The
Tempest, the entire action takes place in the second world. In Measure
for Measure the Duke disappears from the action and returns at the
end; The Tempest seems to present the same type of action
inside out, as the entire cast follows Prospero into his retreat, and is shaped
into a new social order there.
These five phases of comedy may be seen as a sequence of stages in the
life of a redeemed society. Purely ironic comedy exhibits this society in its
infancy, swaddled and smothered by the society it should replace. Quixotic
comedy exhibits it in adolescence, still too ignorant of the ways of the world
to impose itself. In the third phase it comes to maturity and triumphs; in the
fourth it is already mature and established. In the fifth it is part of a
settled order which has been there from the beginning, an order which takes on
an increasingly religious cast and seems to be drawing away from human
experience altogether. At this point the undisplaced commedia, the
vision of Dante's Paradiso, moves out of our circle ofmythoi into
the apocalyptic or abstract mythical world above it. At this point we realize
that the crudest of Plautine comedy-formulas has much the same structure as the
central Christian myth itself, with its divine son appeasing the wrath of a
father and redeeming what is at once a society and a bride.
At this point too comedy proper enters its final or sixth phase, the
phase of the collapse and disintegration of the comic society. In this phase
the social units of comedy become small and esoteric, or even confined to a
single individual. Secret and sheltered places, forests in moonlight, secluded
valleys, and happy islands become more prominent, as does the penseroso mood
of romance, the love of the occult and the marvellous, the sense of individual
detachment from routine existence. In this kind of comedy we have finally left
the world of wit and the awakened critical intelligence for the opposite pole,
an oracular solemnity which, if we surrender uncritically to it, will provide a
delightful frisson. This is the world of ghost stories, thrillers, and Gothic
romances, and, on a more [185] sophisticated level, the kind of imaginative
withdrawal portrayed in Huysmans' A Rebours. The somberness of Des
Esseintes' surroundings has nothing to do with tragedy: Des Esseintes is a
dilettante trying to amuse himself. The comic society has run the full course
from infancy to death, and in its last phase myths closely connected
psychologically with a return to the womb are appropriate.
The romance is nearest of all
literary forms to the wish-fulfilment dream, and for that reason it has
socially a curiously paradoxical role. In every age the ruling social or
intellectual class tends to project its ideals in some form of romance, where
the virtuous heroes and beautiful heroines represent the ideals and the
villains the threats to their ascendancy. This is the general character of
chivalric romance in the Middle Ages, aristocratic romance in the Renaissance,
bourgeois romance since the eighteenth century, and revolutionary romance in
contemporary Russia. Yet there is a genuinely "proletarian" element
in romance too which is never satisfied with its various incarnations, and in
fact the incarnations themselves indicate that no matter how great a change may
take place in society, romance will turn up again, as hungry as ever, looking
for new hopes and desires to feed on. The perennially child like quality of
romance is marked by its extraordinarily persistent nostalgia, its search for
some kind of imaginative golden age in time or space. There has never to my
knowledge been any period of Gothic English literature, but the list of Gothic
revivalists stretches completely across its entire history, from the Beowulf
poet to writers of our own day.
The essential element of plot in romance is adventure, which means that
romance is naturally a sequential and processional form, hence we know it
better from fiction than from drama. At its most naive it is an endless form in
which a central character who never develops or ages goes through one adventure
after an other until the author himself collapses. We see this form in comic
strips, where the central characters persist for years in a state of
refrigerated deathlessness. However, no book can rival the continuity of the
newspaper, and as soon as romance achieves a literary form, it tends to limit
itself to a sequence of minor [186] adventures leading up to a major or
climacteric adventure, usually announced from the beginning, the completion of
which rounds off the story. We may call this major adventure, the element that
gives literary form to the romance, the quest.
The complete form of the romance is clearly the successful quest, and
such a completed form has three main stages: the stage of the perilous journey
and the preliminary minor adventures; the crucial struggle, usually some kind
of battle in which either the hero or his foe, or both, must die; and the
exaltation of the hero. We may call these three stages respectively, using
Greek terms, the agon or conflict, the pathos or
death-struggle, and the anagnorisis or discovery, the
recognition of the hero, who has clearly proved himself to be a hero even if he
does not survive the conflict. Thus the romance expresses more clearly the
passage from struggle through a point of ritual death to a recognition scene
that we discovered in comedy. A threefold structure is repeated in many
features of romance in the frequency, for instance, with which the successful
hero is a third son, or the third to undertake the quest, or successful on his
third attempt. It is shown more directly in the three-day rhythm of death,
disappearance and revival which is found in the myth of Attis and other dying
gods, and has been incorporated in our Easter.
A quest involving conflict assumes two main characters, a protagonist or
hero, and an antagonist or enemy. (No doubt I should add, for the benefit of
some readers, that I have read the article "Protagonist" in
Fowler's Modern English Usage.) The enemy may be an ordinary human
being, but the nearer the romance is to myth, the more attributes of divinity
will cling to the hero and the more the enemy will take on demonic mythical
qualities. The central form of romance is dialectical: everything is focussed
on a conflict between the hero and his enemy, and all the reader's values are
bound up with the hero. Hence the hero of romance is analogous to the mythical
Messiah or deliverer who comes from an upper world, and his enemy is analogous
to the demonic powers of a lower world. The conflict however takes place in, or
at any rate primarily concerns, our world, which is in the middle, and which is
characterized by the cyclical movement of nature. Hence the opposite poles of
the cycles of nature are assimilated to the opposition of the hero and his
enemy. The enemy is associated with winter, darkness, confusion, sterility,
moribund life, [187] and old age, and the hero with spring, dawn, order,
fertility, vigor, and youth. As all the cyclical phenomena can be readily
associated or identified, it follows that any attempt to prove that a romantic
story does or does not resemble, say, a solar myth, or that its hero does or
does not resemble a sun-god, is likely to be a waste of time. If it is a story
within this general area, cyclical imagery is likely to be present, and solar
imagery is normally prominent among cyclical images. If the hero of a romance
returns from a quest disguised, flings off his beggar's rags, and stands forth
in the resplendent scarlet cloak of the prince, we do not have a theme which
has necessarily descended from a solar myth; we have the literary device of
displacement. The hero does something which we may or may not, as we like,
associate with the myth of the sun returning at dawn. If we are reading the
story as critics, with an eye to structural principles, we shall make the
association, because the solar analogy explains why the hero's act is an
effective and conventional incident. If we are reading the story for fun, we
need not bother: that is, some murky "subconscious" factor in our
response will take care of the association.
We have distinguished myth from romance by the hero's power of action:
in the myth proper he is divine, in the romance proper he is human. This
distinction is much sharper theologically than it is poetically, and myth and
romance both belong in the general category of mythopoeic literature. The
attributing of divinity to the chief characters of myth, however, tends to give
myth a further distinction, already referred to, of occupying a central
canonical position. Most cultures regard certain stories with more reverence
than others, either because they are thought of as historically true or because
they have come to bear a heavier weight of conceptual meaning. The story of
Adam and Eve in Eden has thus a canonical position for poets in our tradition
whether they believe in its historicity or not. The reason for the greater
profundity of canonical myth is not solely tradition, but the result of the
greater degree of metaphorical identification that is possible is myth. In
literary criticism the myth is normally the metaphorical key to the
displacements of romance, hence the importance of the quest-myth of the Bible
in what follows. But because of the tendency to expurgate and moralize in
canonical myth, the less inhibited area of legend and folk tale often contains
an equally great concentration of mythical meaning. [188]
The central form of quest-romance is the dragon-killing theme
exemplified in the stories of St. George and Perseus, already referred to. A
land ruled by a helpless old king is laid waste by a sea-monster, to whom one
young person after another is offered to be devoured, until the lot falls on
the king's daughter: at that point the hero arrives, kills the dragon, marries
the daughter, and succeeds to the kingdom. Again, as with comedy, we have a
simple pattern with many complex elements. The ritual analogies of the myth
suggest that the monster is the sterility of the land itself, and that the
sterility of the land is present in the age and impotence of the king, who is
sometimes suffering from an incurable malady or wound, like Amfortas in Wagner.
His position is that of Adonis overcome by the boar of winter, Adonis's
traditional thigh-wound being as close to castration symbolically as it is
anatomically.
In the Bible we have a sea-monster usually named leviathan, who is
described as the enemy of the Messiah, and whom the Messiah is destined to kill
in the "day of the Lord." The leviathan is the source of social
sterility, for it is identified with Egypt and Babylon, the oppressors of
Israel, and is described in the Book of Job as "king over all the children
of pride." It also seems closely associated with the natural sterility of
the fallen world, with the blasted world of struggle and poverty and disease
into which Job is hurled by Satan and Adam by the serpent in Eden. In the Book
of Job God's revelation to Job consists largely of descriptions of the
leviathan and a slightly less sinister land cousin named behemoth. These
monsters thus apparently represent the fallen order of nature over which Satan
has some control. (I am trying to make sense of the meaning of the Book of Job
as we now have it, on the assumption that whoever was responsible for its
present version had some reason for producing that version. Guesswork about
what the poem may originally have been or meant is useless, as it is only the
version we know that has had any influence on our literature.) In the Book of
Revelation the leviathan, Satan, and the Edenic serpent are all identified.
This identification is the basis for an elaborate dragon-killing metaphor in
Christian symbolism in which the hero is Christ (often represented in art
standing on a prostrate monster), the dragon Satan, the impotent old king Adam,
whose son Christ becomes, and the rescued bride the Church. [189]
Now if the leviathan is the whole fallen world of sin and death and
tyranny into which Adam fell, it follows that Adam's children are born, live,
and die inside his belly. Hence if the Messiah is to deliver us by killing the
leviathan, he releases us. In the folk tale versions of dragon-killing stories
we notice how frequently the previous victims of the dragon come out of him
alive after he is killed. Again, if we are inside the dragon, and the hero
comes to help us, the image is suggested of the hero going down the monster's
open throat, like Jonah (whom Jesus accepted as a prototype of himself), and
returning with his redeemed behind him. Hence the symbolism of the Harrowing of
Hell, hell being regularly represented in iconography by the "toothed
gullet of an aged shark," to quote a modern reference to it. Secular versions
of journeys inside monsters occur from Lucian to our day, and perhaps even the
Trojan horse had originally some links with the same theme. The image of the
dark winding labyrinth for the monster's belly is a natural one, and one that
frequently appears in heroic quests, notably that of Theseus. A less displaced
version of the story of Theseus would have shown him emerging from the
labyrinth at the head of a procession of the Athenian youths and maidens
previously sacrificed to the Minotaur. In many solar myths, too, the hero
travels perilously through a dark labyrinthine underworld full of monsters
between sunset and sunrise. This theme may be come a structural principle of
fiction on any level of sophistication. One would expect to find it in fairy tales
or children's stories, and in fact if we "stand back" from Tom Sawyer
we can see a youth with no father or mother emerging with a maiden from a
labyrinthine cave, leaving a bat-eating demon imprisoned behind him. But in the
most complex and elusive of the later stories of Henry James, The Sense
of the Past, the same theme is used, the labyrinthine underworld being in
this case a period of past time from which the hero is released by the
sacrifice of a heroine, an Ariadne figure. In this story, as in many folktales,
the motif of the two brothers connected by sympathetic magic of some sort is
also employed.
In the Old Testament the Messiah-figure of Moses leads his people out of
Egypt. The Pharaoh of Egypt is identified with the leviathan by Ezekiel, and the
fact that the infant Moses was rescued by Pharaoh's daughter gives to the
Pharaoh something of the role of the cruel father-figure who seeks the hero's
death, a role [190] also taken by the raging Herod of the miracle plays. Moses
and the Israelites wander through a labyrinthine desert, after which the reign
of the law ends and the conquest of the Promised Land is achieved by Joshua,
whose name is the same as that of Jesus. Thus when the angel Gabriel tells the
Virgin to call her son Jesus, the typological meaning is that the era of the
law is over, and the assault on the Promised Land is about to begin. There are
thus two concentric quest-myths in the Bible, a Genesis-apocalypse myth and an
Exodus-millennium myth. In the former Adam is cast out of Eden, loses the river
of life and the tree of life, and wanders in the labyrinth of human history
until he is restored to his original state by the Messiah. In the latter Israel
is cast out of his inheritance and wanders in the labyrinths of Egyptian and
Babylonian captivity until he is restored to his original state in the Promised
Land. Eden and the Promised Land, therefore, are typologically identical, as
are the tyrannies of Egypt and Babylon and the wilderness of the law. Paradise
Regained deals with the temptation of Christ by Satan, which is, Michael tells
us in Paradise Lost, the true form of the dragon-killing myth assigned to the
Messiah. Christ is in the situation of Israel under the law, wandering in the
wilderness: his victory is at once the conquest of the Promised Land typified
by his namesake Joshua and the raising of Eden in the wilderness.
The leviathan is usually a sea-monster, which means metaphorically that
he is the sea, and the prophecy that the Lord will hook and
land the leviathan in Ezekiel is identical with the prophecy in Revelation that
there shall be no more sea. As denizens of his belly, therefore, we are also
metaphorically under water. Hence the importance of fishing in the Gospels, the
apostles being "fishers of men" who cast their nets into the sea of
this world. Hence, too, the later development, referred to in The Waste Land,
of Adam or the impotent king as an ineffectual "fisher king." In the
same poem the appropriate link is also made with Prospero's rescuing of a society
out of the sea in The Tempest. In other comedies, too, ranging from
Sakuntala to Rudens, something indispensable to the action or the cognitio is
fished out of the sea, and many quest heroes, including Beowulf, achieve their
greatest feats under water. The insistence on Christ's ability to command the
sea belongs to the same aspect of symbolism. And as the leviathan, in his
aspect as the fallen world, contains all forms of [191] life imprisoned within
himself, so as the sea he contains the imprisoned life-giving rain waters whose
coming marks the spring. The monstrous animal who swallows all the water in the
world and is then teased or tricked or forced into disgorging it is a favorite
of folk tales, and a Mesopotamian version lies close behind the story of Creation
in Genesis. In many solar myths the sun god is represented as sailing in a boat
on the surface of our world.
Lastly, if the leviathan is death, and the hero has to enter the body of
death, the hero has to die, and if his quest is completed the final stage of it
is, cyclically, rebirth, and, dialectically, resurrection. In the St. George
plays the hero dies in his dragon-fight and is brought to life by a doctor, and
the same symbolism runs through all the dying-god myths. There are thus not
three but four distinguishable aspects to the quest-myth. First, the agon or
conflict itself. Second, the pathos or death, often the mutual
death of hero and monster. Third, the disappearance of the hero, a theme which
often takes the form of sparagmos or tearing to pieces. Some
times the hero's body is divided among his followers, as in Eucharist
symbolism: sometimes it is distributed around the natural world, as in the
stories of Orpheus and more especially Osiris. Fourth, the reappearance and
recognition of the hero, where sacramental Christianity follows the
metaphorical logic: those who in the fallen world have partaken of their
redeemer's divided body are united with his risen body.
The four mythoi that we are dealing with, comedy,
romance, tragedy, and irony, may now be seen as four aspects of a central
unifying myth.Agon or conflict is the basis or archetypal theme of
romance, the radical of romance being a sequence of marvellous
adventures. Pathos or catastrophe, whether in triumph or in
defeat, is the archetypal theme of tragedy. Sparagmos, or the sense
that heroism and effective action are absent, disorganized or foredoomed to
defeat, and that confusion and anarchy reign over the world, is the archetypal
theme of irony and satire.Anagnorisis, or recognition of a newborn
society rising in triumph around a still somewhat mysterious hero and his
bride, is the archetypal theme of comedy.
We have spoken of the Messianic hero as a redeemer of society, but in
the secular quest-romances more obvious motives and rewards for the quest are
more common. Often the dragon guards [192] a hoard: the quest for buried
treasure has been a central theme of romance from the Siegfried cycle to
Nostromo, and is unlikely to be exhausted yet. Treasure means wealth, which in
mythopoeic romance often means wealth in its ideal forms, power and wisdom. The
lower world, the world inside or behind the guarding dragon, is often inhabited
by a prophetic sibyl, and is a place of oracles and secrets, such as Woden was
willing to mutilate himself to obtain. Mutilation or physical handicap, which
combines the themes of sparagmos and ritual death, is often the price of
unusual wisdom or power, as it is in the figure of the crippled smith Weyland
or Hephaistos, and in the story of the blessing of Jacob. The Arabian Nights
are full of stories of what may be called the etiology of mutilation. Again,
the reward of the quest usually is or includes a bride. This bride-figure is
ambiguous: her psychological connection with the mother in an Oedipus fantasy is
more insistent than in comedy. She is often to be found in a perilous,
forbidden, or tabooed place, like Brunnhilde's wall of fire or the sleeping
beauty's wall of thorns, and she is, of course, often rescued from the
unwelcome embraces of another and generally older male, or from giants or
bandits or other usurpers. The removal of some stigma from the heroine figures
prominently in romance as in comedy, and ranges from the "loathly
lady" theme of Chaucer's Wife of Bath's Tale to the
forgiven harlot of the Book of Hosea. The "black but comely" bride of
the Song of Songs belongs in the same complex.
The quest-romance has analogies to both rituals and dreams, and the
rituals examined by Frazer and the dreams examined by Jung show the remarkable
similarity in form that we should expect of two symbolic structures analogous
to the same thing. Translated into dream terms, the quest-romance is the search
of the libido or desiring self for a fulfilment that will deliver it from the
anxieties of reality but will still contain that reality. The antagonists of
the quest are often sinister figures, giants, ogres, witches and magicians,
that clearly have a parental origin; and yet redeemed and emancipated paternal
figures are involved too, as they are in the psychological quests of both Freud
and Jung. Translated into ritual terms, the quest-romance is the victory of
fertility over the waste land. Fertility means food and drink, bread and wine,
body and blood, the union of male and female. The precious objects brought back
from the quest, or seen or obtained as a result of it, [193] sometimes combine
the ritual and the psychological associations. The Holy Grail, for instance, is
connected with Christian Eucharist symbolism; it is related to or descended
from a miraculous food- provider like the cornucopia, and, like other cups and
hollow vessels, it has female sexual affinities, its masculine counterpart
being, we are told, the bleeding lance. The pairing of solid food and liquid
refreshment recurs in the edible tree and the water of life in the Biblical
apocalypse.
We may take the first book of The Faerie Queene as
representing perhaps the closest following of the Biblical quest-romance theme
in English literature: it is closer even than The Pilgrims Progress,
which resembles it because they both resemble the Bible. Attempts to compare
Bunyan and Spenser without reference to the Bible, or to trace their
similarities to a common origin in secular romance, are more or less perverse.
In Spenser's account of the quest of St. George, the patron saint of England,
the protagonist represents the Christian Church in England, and hence his quest
is an imitation of that of Christ. Spenser's Redcross Knight is led by the lady
Una (who is veiled in black) to the kingdom of her parents, which is being laid
waste by a dragon. The dragon is of somewhat unusual size, at least
allegorically. We are told that Una's parents held "all the world" in
their control until the dragon "Forwasted all their land, and them
expelled." Una's parents are Adam and Eve; their kingdom is Eden or the
unfallen world, and the dragon, who is the entire fallen world, is identified
with the leviathan, the serpent of Eden, Satan, and the beast of Revelation.
Thus St. George's mission, a repetition of that of Christ, is by killing the
dragon to raise Eden in the wilderness and restore England to the status of
Eden. The association of an ideal England with Eden, assisted by legends of a
happy island in the western ocean and by the similarity of the Hesperides story
to that of Eden, runs through English literature at least from the end of
Greene's Friar Bacon to Blake's "Jerusalem" hymn. St. George's
wanderings with Una, or without her, are parallel to the wandering of the
Israelites in the wilderness, between Egypt and the Promised Land, bearing the
veiled ark of the covenant and yet ready to worship a golden calf.
The battle with the dragon lasts, of course, three days: at the end of
each of the first two days St. George is beaten back and is strengthened, first
by the water of life, then by the tree of life. These represent the two
sacraments which the reformed church [194] accepted; they are the two features
of the garden of Eden to be restored to man in the apocalypse, and they have
also a more general Eucharist connection. St. George's emblem is a red cross on
a white ground, which is the flag borne by Christ in traditional iconography
when he returns in triumph from the prostrate dragon of hell. The red and white
symbolize the two aspects of the risen body, flesh and blood, bread and wine,
and in Spenser they have a historical connection with the union of red and
white roses in the reigning head of the church. The link between the
sacramental and the sexual aspects of the red and white symbolism is indicated
in alchemy, with which Spenser was clearly acquainted, in which a crucial phase
of the production of the elixir of immortality is known as the union of the red
king and the white queen.
The characterization of romance follows its general dialectic structure,
which means that subtlety and complexity are not much favored. Characters tend
to be either for or against the quest. If they assist it they are idealized as
simply gallant or pure; if they obstruct it they are caricatured as simply
villainous or cowardly. Hence every typical character in romance tends to have
his moral opposite confronting him, like black and white pieces in a chess
game. In romance the "white" pieces who strive for the quest
correspond to the eiron group in comedy, though the word is no longer appropriate,
as irony has little place in romance. Romance has a counterpart to the
benevolent retreating eiron of comedy in its figure of the "old wise
man," as Jung calls him, like Prospero, Merlin, or the palmer of Spenser's
second quest, often a magician who affects the action he watches over. The
Arthur of The Faerie Queene, though not an old man, has this function. He has a
feminine counterpart in the sibylline wise mother-figure, often a potential
bride like Solveig in Peer Gynt, who sits quietly at home waiting for the hero
to finish his wanderings and come back to her. This latter figure is often the
lady for whose sake or at whose bidding the quest is performed: she is
represented by the Faerie Queene in Spenser and by Athene in the Perseus story.
These are the king and queen of the white pieces, though their power of
movement is of course reversed in actual chess. The disadvantage of making the
queen-figure the hero's mistress, in anything more than a political sense, is
that she spoils his fun with the distressed damsels he meets on his journey,
who are often enticingly tied [195] naked to rocks or trees, like Andromeda or
Angelica in Ariosto. A polarization may thus be set up between the lady of duty
and the lady of pleasure -- we have already glanced at a late development of
this in the light and dark heroines of Victorian romance. One simple way out is
to make the former the latter's mother-in-law: a theme of reconciliation after
enmity and jealousy most commonly results, as in the relations of Psyche and
Venus in Apuleius. Where there is no reconciliation, the older female remains
sinister, the cruel stepmother of folk tale.
The evil magician' and the witch, Spenser's Archimago and Duessa, are
the black king and queen. The latter is appropriately called by Jung the
"terrible mother," and he associates her with the fear of incest and
with such hags as Medusa who seem to have a suggestion of erotic perversion
about them. The redeemed figures, apart from the bride, are generally too weak to
be strongly characterized. The faithful companion or shadow figure of the hero
has his opposite in the traitor, the heroine her opposite in the siren or
beautiful witch, the dragon his opposite in the friendly or helping animals
that are so conspicuous in romance, among which the horse who gets the hero to
his quest has naturally a central place. The conflict of son and father that we
noted in comedy recurs in romance: in the Bible the second Adam comes to the
rescue of the first one, and in the Grail cycle the pure son Galahad
accomplishes what his impure father Lancelot failed in.
The characters who elude the moral antithesis of heroism and villainy
generally are or suggest spirits of nature. They represent partly the moral
neutrality of the intermediate world of nature and partly a world of mystery
which is glimpsed but never seen, and which retreats when approached. Among
female characters of this type are the shy nymphs of Classical legends and the
elusive half-wild creatures who might be called daughter-figures, and include
Spenser's Florimell, Hawthorne's Pearl, Wagner's Kundry, and Hudson's Rima.
Their male counterparts have a little more variety. Kipling's Mowgli is the
best known of the wild boys; a green man lurked in the forests of medieval
England, appearing as Robin Hood and as the knight of Gawain's adventure; the "salvage
man," represented in Spenser by Satyrane, is a Renaissance favorite, and
the awkward but faithful giant with unkempt hair has shambled amiably through
romance for centuries.
Such characters are, more or less, children of nature, who can [196] be
brought to serve the hero, like Crusoe's Friday, but retain the inscrutability
of their origin. As servants or friends of the hero, they impart the mysterious
rapport with nature that so often marks the central figure of romance. The
paradox that many of these children of nature are "supernatural"
beings is not as distressing in romance as in logic. The helpful fairy, the
grateful dead man, the wonderful servant who has just the abilities the hero
needs in a crisis, are all folk tale commonplaces. They are romantic
intensifications of the comic tricky slave, the author's architectus. In James
Thurber's The Thirteen Clocks this character type is called the
"Golux," and there is no reason why the word should not be adopted as
a critical term.
In romance, as in comedy, there seem to be four poles of
characterization. The struggle of the hero with his enemy corresponds to the
comic contest of eiron and alazon. In the nature-spirits just referred to we
find the parallel in romance to the buffoon or master of ceremonies in comedy:
that is, their function is to intensify and provide a focus for the romantic
mood. It remains to be seen if there is a character in romance corresponding to
the agroikos type in comedy, the refuser of festivity or rustic clown.
Such a character would call attention to realistic aspects of life, like
fear in the presence of danger, which threaten the unity of the romantic mood.
St. George and Una in Spenser are accompanied by a dwarf who carries a bag of
"needments." He is not a traitor, like the other bag-carrier Judas
Iscariot, but he is "fearful," and urges retreat when the going is
difficult. This dwarf with his needments represents, in the dream world of
romance, the shrunken and wizened form of practical waking reality: the more realistic
the story, the more important such a figure would become, until, when we reach
the opposite pole in Don Quixote, he achieves his apotheosis as Sancho Panza.
In other romances we find fools and jesters who are licensed to show fear or
make realistic comments, and who provide a localized safety valve for realism
without allowing it to disrupt the conventions of romance. In Malory a similar
role is assumed by Sir Dinadan, who, it is carefully explained, is really a
gallant knight as well as a jester: hence when he makes jokes "the king
and Launcelot laughed that they might not sit" the suggestion of excessive
and hysterical laughter being psychologically very much to the point. [197]
Romance, like comedy, has six isolatable phases, and as it moves from
the tragic to the comic area, the first three are parallel to the first three
phases of tragedy and the second three to the second three phases of comedy,
already examined from the comic point of view. The phases form a cyclical
sequence in a romantic hero's life.
The first phase is the myth of the birth of the hero, the morphology of
which has been studied in some detail in folklore. This myth is often
associated with a flood, the regular symbol of the beginning and the end of a
cycle. The infant hero is often placed in an ark or chest floating on the sea,
as in the story of Perseus; from there he drifts to land, as in the exordium to
Beowulf, or is rescued from among reeds and bulrushes on a river bank, as in
the story of Moses. A landscape of water, boat, and reeds appears at the
beginning of Dante's journey up the mount of Purgatory, where there are many
suggestions that the soul is in that stage a newborn infant. On dry land the
infant may be rescued either from or by an animal, and many heroes are nurtured
by animals in a forest during their nonage. When Goethe's Faust begins to look
for his Helena, he searches in the reeds of the Peneus, and then finds a
centaur who carried her to safety on his back when she was a child.
Psychologically, this image is related to the embryo in the womb, the
world of the unborn often being thought of as liquid; anthropologically, it is
related to the image of seeds of new life buried in a dead world of snow or
swamp. The dragon's treasure hoard is closely linked with this mysterious
infant life enclosed in a chest. The fact that the real source of wealth is
potential fertility or new life, vegetable or human, has run through romance
from ancient myths to Ruskin's King of the Golden River, Ruskin's treatment of
wealth in his economic works being essentially a commentary on this fairy tale.
A similar association of treasure hoard and infant life appears in more
plausible guise in Silas Marner. The long literary history of the theme of
mysterious parentage from Euripides to Dickens has already been mentioned.
In the Bible the end of a historical cycle and the birth of a new one is
marked by parallel symbols. First we have a universal deluge and an ark, with
the potency of all future life contained in it, floating on the waters; then we
have the story of the Egyptian host drowned in the Red Sea and the Israelites
set free to carry their [198] ark through the wilderness, an image adopted by
Dante as the basis of his purgatorial symbolism. The New Testament begins with
an infant in a manger, and the tradition of depicting the world outside as sunk
in snow relates the Nativity to the same archetypal phase. Images of returning
spring soon follow: the rainbow in the Noah story, the bringing of water out of
a rock by Moses, the baptism of Christ, all show the turning of the cycle from
the wintry water of death to the reviving waters of life. The providential
birds, the raven and dove in the Noah story, the ravens feeding Elijah in the
wilderness, the dove hovering over Jesus, belong to the same complex.
Often, too, there is a search for the child, who has to be hidden away
in a secret place. The hero being of mysterious origin, his true paternity is
often concealed, and a false father appears who seeks the child's death. This
is the role of Acrisius in the Perseus story, of the Cronos of Hesiodic myth
who tries to swallow his children, of the child-killing Pharaoh in the Old
Testament, and of Herod in the New. In later fiction he often modulates to the
usurping wicked uncle who appears several times in Shakespeare. The mother is
thus often the victim of jealousy, persecuted or calumniated like the mother of
Perseus or like Constance in the Man of Law's Tale. This version is very close
psychologically to the theme of the rivalry of the son and a hateful father for
possession of the mother. The theme of the calumniated girl ordered out of the
house with her child by a cruel father, generally into the snow, still drew
tears from audiences of Victorian melodramas, and literary developments of the
theme of the hunted mother in the same period extend from Eliza crossing the
ice in Uncle Tom's Cabin to Adam Bede and Far from the Madding Crowd. The false
mother, the celebrated cruel stepmother, is also common: her victim is of
course usually female, and the resulting conflict is portrayed in many ballads
and folktales of the Cinderella type. The true father is sometimes represented
by a wise old man or teacher: this is the relation of Prospero to Ferdinand, as
well as of Chiron the centaur to Achilles. The double of the true mother
appears in the daughter of Pharaoh who adopts Moses, In more realistic modes
the cruel parent speaks with the voice of, or takes the form of, a
narrow-minded public opinion.
The second phase brings us to the innocent youth of the hero, a phase
most familiar to us from the story of Adam and Eve in [199] Eden before the
Fall. In literature this phase presents a pastoral and Arcadian world,
generally a pleasant wooded landscape, full of glades, shaded valleys,
murmuring brooks, the moon, and other images closely linked with the female or
maternal aspect of sexual imagery. Its heraldic colors are green and gold,
traditionally the colors of vanishing youth: one thinks of Sandburg's poem
Between Two Worlds. It is often a world of magic or desirable law, and it tends
to center on a youthful hero, still overshadowed by parents, surrounded by
youthful companions. The archetype of erotic innocence is less commonly
marriage than the kind of "chaste" love that precedes marriage; the
love of brother for sister, or of two boys for each other. Hence, though in
later phases it is often recalled as a lost happy time or Golden Age, the sense
of being close to a moral taboo is very frequent, as it is of course in the
Eden story itself. Johnson's Rasselas, Poe's Eleanora, and Blake's Book of Thel
introduce us to a kind of prison-Paradise or unborn world from which the
central characters long to escape to a lower world, and the same feeling of
malaise and longing to enter a world of action recurs in the most exhaustive
treatment of the phase in English literature, Keats's Endymion.
The theme of the sexual barrier in this phase takes many forms: the
serpent of the Eden story recurs in Green Mansions, and a barrier of fire
separates Amoret in Spenser from her lover Scudamour. At the end of the
Purgatorio the soul reaches again its unfallen childhood or lost Golden Age,
and Dante consequently finds him self in the garden of Eden, separated from the
young girl Matelda by the river Lethe. The dividing river recurs in William
Morris's curious story The Sundering Flood, where an arrow shot over it has to
do for the symbol of sexual contact. In Kubla Khan, which is closely related
both to the Eden story in Paradise Lost and to Rasselas, a "sacred
river" is closely followed by the distant vision of a singing damsel.
Melville's Pierre opens with a sardonic parody of this phase, the hero still
dominated by his mother but calling her his sister. A good deal of the imagery
of this world may be found in the sixth book of The Faerie Queene, especially
in the stories of Tristram and Pastorella.
The third phase is the normal quest theme that we have been discussing,
and needs no further comment at this point. The fourth phase corresponds to the
fourth phase of comedy, in which the happier society is more or less visible
throughout the action instead [200] of emerging only in the last few moments.
In romance the central theme of this phase is that of the maintaining of the
integrity of the innocent world against the assault of experience. It thus
often takes the form of a moral allegory, such as we have in Milton's Comus,
Bunyan's Holy War, and many morality plays, including The Castell of
Perseveraunce. The much simpler scheme of the Canterbury Tales, where the only
conflict is to preserve the mood of holiday and festivity against bickering,
seems for some reason to be less frequent.
The integrated body to be defended may be individual or social, or both.
The individual aspect of it is presented in the allegory of temperance in the
second book of The Faerie Queene, which forms a natural sequel to the first
book, dealing as it does with the more difficult theme of consolidating heroic
innocence in this world after the first great quest has been completed. Guyon,
the knight of temperance, has as his main antagonists Acrasia, the mistress of
the Bower of Bliss, and Mammon. These represent "Beauty and money,"
in their aspects as instrumental goods perverted into external goals. The
temperate mind contains its good within itself, continence being its
prerequisite, hence it belongs to what we have called the innocent world. The
intemperate mind seeks its good in the external object of the world of
experience. Both temperance and intemperance could be called natural, but one
belongs to nature as an order and the other to nature as a fallen world.
Comus's temptation of the Lady is based on a similar ambiguity in the meaning
of nature. A central image in this phase of romance is that of the beleaguered
castle, represented in Spenser by the House of Alma, which is described in
terms of the economy of the human body.
The social aspect of the same phase is treated in the fifth book of The
Faerie Queene, the legend of justice, where power is the prerequisite of
justice, corresponding to continence in relation to temperance. Here we meet,
in the vision of Isis and Osiris, the fourth-phase image of the monster tamed
and controlled by the virgin, an image which appears episodically in Book One
in connection with Una, who tames satyrs and a lion. The Classical prototype of
it is the Gorgon's head on the shield of Athene. The theme of invincible
innocence or virginity is associated with similar images in literature from the
child leading the beasts of prey in Isaiah to Marina in the brothel in Pericles,
and it reappears in later fictions [201] in which an unusually truculent hero
is brought to heel by the heroine. An ironic parody of the same theme forms the
basis of Aristophanes' Lysistrata.
The fifth phase corresponds to the fifth phase of comedy, and like it is
a reflective, idyllic view of experience from above, in which the movement of
the natural cycle has usually a prominent place. It deals with a world very
similar to that of the second phase except that the mood is a contemplative
withdrawal from or sequel to action rather than a youthful preparation for it.
It is, like the second phase, an erotic world, but it presents experience as
comprehended and not as a mystery. This is the world of most of Morris's
romances, of Hawthorne's Blithedale Romance, of the mature innocent wisdom of
The Franklin's Tale, and of most of the imagery of the third book of The Faerie
Queene. In this last, as well as in the late Shakespearean romances, notably
Pericles, and even The Tempest, we notice a tendency to the moral
stratification of characters. The true lovers are on top of a hierarchy of what
might be called erotic imitations, going down through the various grades of
lust and passion to perversion (Argante and Oliphant in Spenser; Antiochus and
his daughter in Pericles). Such an arrangement of characters is consistent with
the detached and contemplative view of society taken in this phase.
The sixth or penseroso phase is the last phase of romance as of comedy.
In comedy it shows the comic society breaking up into small units or
individuals; in romance it marks the end of a movement from active to
contemplative adventure. A central image of this phase, a favorite of Yeats, is
that of the old man in the tower, the lonely hermit absorbed in occult or
magical studies. On a more popular and social level it takes in what might be
called cuddle fiction: the romance that is physically associated with
comfortable beds or chairs around fireplaces or warm and cosy spots generally.
A characteristic feature of this phase is the tale in quotation marks, where we
have an opening setting -- with a small group of congenial people, and then the
real story told by one of the members. In The Turn of the Screw a large party
is telling ghost stories in a country house; then some people leave, and a much
smaller and more intimate circle gathers around the crucial tale. The opening
dismissal of catechumens is thoroughly in the spirit and conventions of this
phase. The effect of such devices is to present the story through a relaxed and
contemplative haze as something that [202] entertains us without, so to speak,
confronting us, as direct tragedy confronts us.
Collections of tales based on a symposium device like the Decameron
belong here. Morris's Earthly Paradise is a very pure example of the same
phase: there a number of the great archetypal myths of Greek and Northern
culture are personified as a group of old men who forsook the world during the
Middle Ages, refusing to be made either kings or gods ? and who now interchange
their myths in an ineffectual land of dreams. Here the themes of the lonely old
men, the intimate group, and the reported tale are linked. The calendar
arrangement of the tales links it also with the symbolism of the natural cycle.
Another and very concentrated treatment of the phase is Virginia Woolf's
Between the Acts, where a play representing the history of English life is
acted before a group. The history is conceived not only as a progression but as
a cycle of which the audience is the end, and, as the last page indicates, the
beginning as well.
From Wagner's Ring to science fiction, we may notice an increasing
popularity of the flood archetype. This usually takes the form of some cosmic
disaster destroying the whole fictional society except a small group, which
begins life anew in some sheltered spot. The affinities of this theme to that
of the cosy group which has managed to shut the rest of the world out are clear
enough, and it brings us around again to the image of the mysterious newborn
infant floating on the sea.
One important detail in poetic symbolism remains to be considered. This
is the symbolic presentation of the point at which the undisplaced apocalyptic
world and the cyclical world of nature come into alignment, and which we
propose to call the point of epiphany. Its most common settings are the
mountain-top, the island, the tower, the lighthouse, and the ladder or
staircase. Folk tales and mythologies are full of stories of an original
connection between heaven or the sun and earth. We have ladders of arrows,
ropes pecked in two by mischievous birds, and the like: such stories are often
analogues of the Biblical stories of the Fall, and survive in Jack's beanstalk,
Rapunzel's hair, and even the curious bit of floating folklore known as the
Indian rope trick. The movement from one world to the other may be symbolized
by the golden fire that descends from the sun, as in the mythical basis of the
Danae [203] story, and by its human response, the fire kindled on the
sacrificial altar. The "gold bug" in Poe's story, which reminds us
that the Egyptian scarab was a solar emblem, is dropped from above on the end
of a string through the eyehole of a skull on a tree and falls on top of a
buried treasure: the archetype here is closely related to the complex of images
we are dealing with, especially to some alchemical versions of it.
In the Bible we have Jacob's ladder, which in Paradise Lost is
associated with Milton's cosmological diagram of a spherical cosmos hanging
from heaven with a hole in the top. There are several mountain-top epiphanies
in the Bible, the Transfiguration being the most notable, and the mountain
vision of Pisgah, the end of the road through the wilderness from which Moses
saw the distant Promised Land, is typologically linked. As long as poets
accepted the Ptolemaic universe, the natural place for the point of epiphany
was a mountain-top just under the moon, the lowest heavenly body. Purgatory in
Dante is an enormous mountain with a path ascending spirally around it, on top
of which, as the pilgrim gradually recovers his lost innocence and casts off
his original sin ? is the garden of Eden. It is at this point that the
prodigious apocalyptic epiphany of the closing cantos of the Purgatorio is
achieved. The sense of being between an apocalyptic world above and a cyclical
world below is present too, as from the garden of Eden all seeds of vegetable
life fall back into the world, while human life passes on.
In The Faerie Queene there is a Pisgah vision in the first book, when
St. George climbs the mountain of contemplation and sees the heavenly city from
a distance. As the dragon he has to kill is the fallen world, there is a level
of the allegory in which his dragon is the space between himself and the
distant city. In the corresponding episode of Ariosto the link between the
mountain-top and the sphere of the moon is clearer. But Spenser's fullest
treatment of the theme is the brilliant metaphysical comedy known as the
Mutabilitie Cantoes, where the conflict of being and becoming, Jove and Mutability,
order and change, is resolved at the sphere of the moon. Mutability's evidence
consists of the cyclical movements of nature, but this evidence is turned
against her and proved to be a principle of order in nature instead of mere
change. In this poem the relation of the heavenly bodies to the apocalyptic
world is not metaphorical identification, as it is, at least as a poetic
convention, in Dante's Paradiso, but likeness: they are still within nature,
and [204] only in the final stanza of the poem does the real apocalyptic world
appear.
The distinction of levels here implies that there may be analogous forms
of the point of epiphany. For instance, it may be presented in erotic terms as
a place of sexual fulfilment, where there is no apocalyptic vision but simply a
sense of arriving at the summit of experience in nature. This natural form of
the point of epiphany is called in Spenser the Gardens of Adonis. It recurs
under that name in Keats's Endymion and is the world entered by the lovers at
the end of Shelley's Revolt of Islam. The Gardens of Adonis, like Eden in
Dante, are a place of seed, into which everything subject to the cyclical order
of nature enters at death and proceeds from at birth. Milton's early poems are,
like the Mutabilitie Cantoes, full of the sense of a distinction between nature
as a divinely sanctioned order, the nature of the music of the spheres, and
nature as a fallen and largely chaotic world. The former is symbolized by the
Gardens of Adonis in Comus, from whence the attendant spirit descends to watch
over the Lady. The central image of this archetype, Venus watching over Adonis,
is (to use a modern distinction) the analogue in terms of Eros to the Madonna
and Son in the context of Agape.
Milton picks up the theme of the Pisgah vision in Paradise Regained,
which assumes an elementary principle of Biblical typology in which the events
of Christ's life repeat those of the history of Israel. Israel goes to Egypt,
brought down by Joseph, escapes a slaughter of innocents, is cut off from Egypt
by the Red Sea, organizes into twelve tribes, wanders forty years in the
wilderness, receives the law from Sinai, is saved by a brazen serpent on a
pole, crosses the Jordan, and enters the Promised Land under "Joshua, whom
the Gentiles Jesus call." Jesus goes to Egypt in infancy, led by Joseph,
escapes a slaughter of innocents, is baptized and recognized as the Messiah,
wanders forty days in the wilderness, gathers twelve followers, preaches the
Sermon on the Mount, saves man kind by dying on a pole, and thereby conquers
the Promised Land as the real Joshua. In Milton the temptation corresponds to
the Pisgah vision of Moses, except that the gaze is turned in the opposite
direction. It marks the climax of Jesus' obedience to the law, just before his
active redemption of the world begins, and the sequence of temptations
consolidates the world, flesh, and devil into the single form of Satan, The
point of epiphany is here [205] represented by the pinnacle of the temple, from
which Satan falls away as Jesus remains motionless on top of it. The fall of
Satan reminds us that the point of epiphany is also the top of the wheel of
fortune, the point from which the tragic hero falls. This ironic use of the
point of epiphany occurs in the Bible in the story of the Tower of Babel.
The Ptolemaic cosmos eventually disappeared, but the point of epiphany
did not, though in more recent literature it is often ironically reversed, or
brought to terms with greater demands for credibility. Allowing for this, one
may still see the same archetype in the final mountain-top scene of Ibsen's
When We Dead Awaken and in the central image of Virginia Woolf s To the
Lighthouse. In the later poetry of Yeats and Eliot it becomes a central
unifying image. Such titles as The Tower and The Winding Stair indicate its
importance for Yeats, and the lunar symbolism and the apocalyptic imagery of
The Tower and Sailing to Byzantium are both thoroughly consistent. In Eliot it
is the flame reached in the fire sermon of The Waste Land, in contrast to the
natural cycle which is symbolized by water, and it is also the
"multifoliate rose" of The Hollow Men. Ash Wednesday brings us back
again to the purgatorial winding stair, and Little Gidding to the burning rose,
where there is a descending movement of fire symbolized by the Pentecostal
tongues of flame and an ascending one symbolized by Hercules' pyre and
"shirt of flame."
Thanks as usual to Aristotle, the
theory of tragedy is in considerably better shape than the other three mythoi,
and we can deal with it more briefly, as the ground is more familiar. Without
tragedy, all literary fictions might be plausibly explained as expressions of emotional
attachments, whether of wish-fulfilment or of repugnance: the tragic fiction
guarantees, so to speak, a disinterested quality in literary experience. It is
largely through the tragedies of Greek culture that the sense of the authentic
natural basis of human character comes into literature. In romance the
characters are still largely dream-characters; in satire they tend to be
caricatures; in comedy their actions are twisted to fit the demands of a happy
ending. In full tragedy the main characters are emancipated from dream, an
emancipation which is at the same time a restriction, [206] because the order
of nature is present. However thickly strewn a tragedy may be with ghosts,
portents, witches, or oracles, we know that the tragic hero cannot simply rub a
lamp and summon a genie to get him out of his trouble.
Like comedy, tragedy is best and most easily studied in drama, but it is
not confined to drama, nor to actions that end in disaster. Plays that are
usually called or classified with tragedies end in serenity, like Cymbeline,
or even joy, like Alcestis or Racine's Esther, or
in an ambiguous mood that is hard to define, like Philoctetes. On
the other hand, while a predominantly sombre mood forms part of the unity of
the tragic structure, concentrating on mood does not intensify the tragic
effect: if it did, Titus Andronicus might well be the most
powerful of Shakespeare's tragedies. The source of tragic effect must be
sought, as Aristotle pointed out, in the tragic mythos or
plot-structure.
It is a commonplace of criticism that comedy tends to deal with
characters in a social group, whereas tragedy is more concentrated on a single
individual. We have given reasons in the first essay for thinking that the
typical tragic hero is somewhere between the divine and the "all too
human." This must be true even of dying gods: Prometheus, being a god,
cannot die, but he suffers for his sympathy with the "dying ones" (brotoi)
or "mortal" men, and even suffering has something subdivine about it.
The tragic hero is very great as compared with us, but there is something else,
something on the side of him opposite the audience, compared to which he is
small. This something else may be called God, gods, fate, accident, fortune,
necessity, circumstance, or any combination of these, but whatever it is the
tragic hero is our mediator with it.
The tragic hero is typically on top of the wheel of fortune, half way
between human society on the ground and the something greater in the sky.
Prometheus, Adam, and Christ hang between heaven and earth, between a world of
paradisal freedom and a world of bondage. Tragic heroes are so much the highest
points in their human landscape that they seem the inevitable conductors of the
power about them, great trees more likely to be struck by lightning than a
clump of grass. Conductors may of course be instruments as well as victims of
the divine lightning: Milton's Samson destroys the Philistine temple with
himself, and Hamlet nearly exterminates the Danish court in his own fall. Something
of Nietzsche's mountain-top air of transvaluation clings to the tragic hero:
his thoughts [207] are not ours any more than his deeds, even if, like Faustus,
he is dragged off to hell for having them. Whatever eloquence or affability he
may have, an inscrutable reserve lies behind it. Even sinister heroes --
Tamburlaine, Macbeth, Creon -- retain this reserve, and we are reminded that
men will die loyally for a wicked or cruel man, but not for an amiable
backslapper. Those who attract most devotion from others are those who are best
able to suggest in their manner that they have no need of it, and from the
urbanity of Hamlet to the sullen ferocity of Ajax, tragic heroes are wrapped in
the mystery of their communion with that something beyond which we can see only
through them, and which is the source of their strength and their fate alike.
In the phrase which so fascinated Yeats, the tragic hero leaves his servants to
do his "living" for him, and the center of tragedy is in the hero's
isolation, not in a villain's betrayal, even when the villain is, as he often
is, a part of the hero himself.
As for the something beyond, its names are variable but the form in
which it manifests itself is fairly constant. Whether the context is Greek,
Christian, or undefined, tragedy seems to lead up to an epiphany of law, of
that which is and must be. It can hardly be an accident that the two great
developments of tragic drama, in fifth-century Athens and in
seventeenth-century Europe, were contemporary with the rise of Ionian and of
Renaissance science. In such a world-view nature is seen as an impersonal
process which human law imitates as best it can, and this direct relation of
man and natural law is in the foreground. The sense in Greek tragedy that fate
is stronger than the gods really implies that the gods exist primarily to
ratify the order of nature, and that if any personality, even a divine one,
possesses a genuine power of veto over law, it is most unlikely that he will
want to exercise it. In Christianity much the same is true of the personality
of Christ in relation to the inscrutable decrees of the Father. Similarly the
tragic process in Shakespeare is natural in the sense that it simply happens,
whatever its cause, explanation, or relationships. Characters may grope about
for conceptions of gods that kill us for their sport, or for a divinity that
shapes our ends, but the action of tragedy will not abide our questions, a fact
often transferred to the personality of Shakespeare.
In its most elementary form, the vision of law (dike) operates
as lex talionis or revenge. The hero provokes enmity, or
inherits a [208] situation of enmity, and the return of the avenger constitutes
the catastrophe. The revenge-tragedy is a simple tragic structure, and like
most simple structures can be a very powerful one, often retained as a central
theme even in the most complex tragedies. Here the original act provoking the
revenge sets up an antithetical or counterbalancing movement, and the
completion of the movement resolves the tragedy. This happens so often that we
may almost characterize the total mythos of tragedy as binary, in contrast to
the three-part saturnalia movement of comedy.
We notice however the frequency of the device of making the revenge come
from another world, through gods or ghosts or oracles. This device expands the
conceptions of both nature and law beyond the limits of the obvious and
tangible. It does not thereby transcend those conceptions, as it is still
natural law that is manifested by the tragic action. Here we see the tragic
hero as disturbing a balance in nature, nature being conceived as an order
stretching over the two kingdoms of the visible and the invisible, a balance
which sooner or later must right itself. The righting of the balance is what the
Greeks called nemesis: again, the agent or instrument of nemesis may
be human vengeance, ghostly vengeance, divine vengeance, divine justice,
accident, fate or the logic of events, but the essential thing is that nemesis happens,
and happens impersonally, unaffected, as Oedipus Tyrannus illustrates,
by the moral quality of human motivation involved. In the Oresteia we
are led from a series of revenge-movements into a final vision of natural law,
a universal compact in which moral law is included and which the gods, in the
person of the goddess of wisdom, endorse. Here nemesis, like its
counterpart the Mosaic law in Christianity, is not abolished but fulfilled: it
is developed from a mechanical or arbitrary sense of restored order,
represented by the Furies, to the rational sense of it expounded by Athene. The
appearance of Athene does not turn the Oresteia into a comedy,
but clarifies its tragic vision.
There are two reductive formulas which have often been used to explain
tragedy. Neither is quite good enough, but each is almost good enough, and as
they are contradictory, they must represent extreme or limiting views of
tragedy. One of these is the theory that all tragedy exhibits the omnipotence
of an external fate. And, of course, the overwhelming majority of tragedies do
leave us with a sense of the supremacy of impersonal power and of the
limitation of human effort. But the fatalistic reduction of tragedy confuses
the [209] tragic condition with the tragic process: fate, in a tragedy,
normally becomes external to the hero only after the tragic process has been
set going. The Greek ananke or moira is in
its normal, or pre-tragic, form the internal balancing condition of life. It
appears as external or antithetical necessity only after it has been violated as
a condition of life, just as justice is the internal condition of an honest
man, but the external antagonist of the criminal. Homer uses a profoundly
significant phrase for the theory of tragedy when he has Zeus speak of
Aegisthus as going hyper moron, beyond fate.
The fatalistic reduction of tragedy does not distinguish tragedy from
irony, and it is again significant that we speak of the irony of fate rather
than of its tragedy. Irony does not need an exceptional central figure: as a
rule, the dingier the hero the sharper the irony, when irony alone is aimed at.
It is the admixture of heroism that gives tragedy its characteristic splendor
and exhilaration. The tragic hero has normally had an extraordinary, often a
nearly divine, destiny almost within his grasp, and the glory of that original
vision never quite fades out of tragedy. The rhetoric of tragedy requires the
noblest diction that the greatest poets can produce, and while catastrophe is
the normal end of tragedy, this is balanced by an equally significant original
greatness, a paradise lost.
The other reductive theory of tragedy is that the act which sets the
tragic process going must be primarily a violation of moral law,
whether human or divine; in short, that Aristotle's hamartia or
"flaw" must have an essential connection with sin or wrongdoing.
Again it is true that the great majority of tragic heroes do possess hubris, a
proud, passionate, obsessed or soaring mind which brings about a morally
intelligible downfall. Such hubris is the normal precipitating agent of
catastrophe, just as in comedy the cause of the happy ending is usually some
act of humility, represented by a slave or by a heroine meanly disguised. In
Aristotle the hamartia of the tragic hero is associated with Aristotle's ethical
conception of proairesis, or free choice of an end, and Aristotle
certainly does tend to think of tragedy as morally, almost physically,
intelligible. It has already been suggested, however, that the conception of
catharsis, which is central to Aristotle's view of tragedy, is inconsistent
with moral reductions of it. Pity and terror are moral feelings, and they are
relevant but not attached to the tragic situation. Shakespeare is particularly
fond of planting moral lightning-rods on both sides of his heroes to deflect
the pity and terror: we have mentioned Othello [210] flanked by Iago and
Desdemona, but Hamlet is flanked by Claudius and Ophelia, Lear by his
daughters, and even Macbeth by Lady Macbeth and Duncan. In all these tragedies
there is a sense of some far-reaching mystery of which this morally
intelligible process is only a part. The hero's act has thrown a switch in a
larger machine than his own life, or even his own society.
All theories of tragedy as morally explicable sooner or later run into the
question: is an innocent sufferer in tragedy (i.e., poetically innocent),
Iphigeneia, Cordelia, Socrates in Plato's Apology, Christ in the Passion, not a
tragic figure? It is not very convincing to try to provide crucial moral flaws
for such characters. Cordelia shows a high spirit, perhaps a touch of
wilfulness, in refusing to flatter her father, and Cordelia gets hanged. Joan
of Arc in Schiller has a moment of tenderness for an English soldier, and Joan
is burned alive, or would have been if Schiller had not decided to sacrifice
the facts to save the face of his moral theory. Here we are getting away from
tragedy, and close to a kind of insane cautionary tale, like Mrs. Pipchin's
little boy who was gored to death by a bull for asking inconvenient questions.
Tragedy, in short, seems to elude the antithesis of moral responsibility and
arbitrary fate, just as it eludes the antithesis of good and evil.
In the third book of Paradise Lost, Milton represents God as
arguing that he made man "Sufficient to have stood, though free to
fall." God knew that Adam would fall, but did not compel him to do so, and
on that basis he disclaims legal responsibility. This argument is so bad that
Milton, if he was trying to escape refutation, did well to ascribe it to God.
Thought and act cannot be so separated: if God had foreknowledge he must have
known in the instant of creating Adam that he was creating a being who would
fall. Yet the passage is a most haunting and suggestive one nonetheless.
For Paradise Lost is not simply an attempt to write one more
tragedy, but to expound what Milton believed to be the archetypal myth of
tragedy. Hence the passage is another example of existential projection: the
real basis of the relation of Milton's God to Adam is the relation of the tragic
poet to his hero. The tragic poet knows that his hero will be in a tragic
situation, but he exerts all his power to avoid the sense of having manipulated
that situation for his own purposes. He exhibits his hero to us as God exhibits
Adam to the angels. If the hero was not sufficient to have stood, the mode is
purely ironic; if he was not free to fall, the mode is purely romantic, [211]
the story of an invincible hero who will conquer all his antagonists as long as
the story is about him. Now most theories of tragedy take one great tragedy as
their norm: thus Aristotle's theory is largely founded on Oedipus
Tyrannus, and Hegel's on Antigone. In seeing the archetypal
human tragedy in the story of Adam, Milton was, of course, in agreement with
the whole Judaeo-Christian cultural tradition, and perhaps arguments drawn from
the story of Adam may have better luck in literary criticism than in subjects
compelled to assume Adam's real existence, either as fact or as a merely legal
fiction. Chaucer's monk, who clearly understood what he was doing, began with
Lucifer and Adam, and we may be well advised to follow his example.
Adam, then, is in a heroic human situation: he is on top of the wheel of
fortune, with the destiny of the gods almost within his reach. He forfeits that
destiny in a way which suggests moral responsibility to some and a conspiracy
of fate to others. What he does is to exchange a fortune of unlimited freedom
for the fate involved in the consequences of the act of exchange, just as, for
a man who deliberately jumps off a precipice, the law of gravitation acts as
fate for the brief remainder of his life. The exchange is presented by Milton
as itself a free act or proairesis, a use of freedom to lose
freedom. And just as comedy often sets up an arbitrary law and then organizes
the action to break or evade it, so tragedy presents the reverse theme of
narrowing a comparatively free life into a process of causation. This happens
to Macbeth when he accepts the logic of usurpation, to Hamlet when he accepts
the logic of revenge, to Lear when he accepts the logic of abdication. The
discovery oranagnorisis which comes at the end of the tragic plot
is not simply the knowledge by the hero of what has happened to him -- Oedipus
Tyrannus, despite its reputation as a typical tragedy, is rather a special
case in that regard -- but the recognition of the determined shape of the life
he has created for himself, with an implicit comparison with the uncreated
potential life he has forsaken. The line of Milton dealing with the fall of the
devils, "O how unlike the place from whence they fell!", referring as
it does both to Virgil's quantum mutatus ab illo and Isaiah's
"How art thou fallen from heaven, O Lucifer son of the morning,"
combines the Classical and the Christian archetypes of tragedy for Satan, of
course, like Adam, possessed an original glory. In Milton the complement to the
vision of Adam on top of the wheel of fortune and [212] falling into the world
of the wheel is Christ standing on the pinnacle of the temple, urged by Satan
to fall, and remaining motion less.
As soon as Adam falls, he enters his own created life ; which is also
the order of nature as we know it. The tragedy of Adam, therefore, resolves,
like all other tragedies, in the manifestation of natural law. He enters a
world in which existence is itself tragic, not existence modified by an act,
deliberate or unconscious. Merely to exist is to disturb the balance of nature.
Every natural man is a Hegelian thesis, and implies a reaction: every new birth
provokes the return of an avenging death. This fact, in itself ironic and now
called Angst, becomes tragic when a sense of a lost and originally higher
destiny is added to it. Aristotle's hamartia, then, is a condition of being,
not a cause of becoming: the reason why Milton ascribes his dubious argument to
God is that he is so anxious to remove God from a predetermined causal
sequence. On one side of the tragic hero is an opportunity for freedom, on the
other the inevitable consequence of losing that freedom. These two sides of
Adam's situation are represented in Milton by the speeches of Raphael and
Michael respectively. Even with an innocent hero or martyr the same situation
arises: in the Passion story it occurs in Christ's prayer in Gethsemane. Tragedy
seems to move up to an Augenblick or crucial moment from which
point the road to what might have been and the road to what will be can be
simultaneously seen. Seen by the audience, that is: it cannot be seen by the
hero if he is in a state of hubris, for in that case the crucial moment is for
him a moment of dizziness, when the wheel of fortune begins its inevitable
cyclical movement downward.
In Adam's situation there is a feeling, which in Christian tradition can
be traced back at least to St. Augustine, that time begins with the fall; that
the fall from liberty into the natural cycle also started the movement of time
as we know it. In other tragedies too we can trace the feeling that nemesis is
deeply involved with the movement of time, whether as the missing of a tide in
the affairs of men, as a recognition that the time is out of joint, as a sense
that time is the devourer of life, the mouth of hell at the previous moment,
when the potential passes forever into the actual, or, in its ultimate horror,
Macbeth's sense of it as simply one clock-tick after another. In comedy time
plays a redeeming role: it uncovers and brings to light what is essential to
the happy ending. 213] The subtitle of Greene's Pandosto, the
source of The Winter's Tale, is "The Triumph of Time,"
and it well describes the nature of Shakespeare's action, where time is
introduced as a chorus. But in tragedy the cognitio is
normally the recognition of the inevitability of a causal sequence in time, and
the forebodings and ironic anticipations surrounding it are based on a sense of
cyclical return.
In irony, as distinct from tragedy, the wheel of time completely
encloses the action, and there is no sense of an original contact with a
relatively timeless world. In the Bible the tragic fall of Adam is followed by
its historical repetition, the fall of Israel into Egyptian bondage, which is,
so to speak, its ironic confirmation. As long as the Geoffrey version of
British history was accepted, the fall of Troy was the corresponding event in
the history of Britain, and, as the fall of Troy began with an idolatrous
misapplication of an apple, there were even symbolic parallels. Shakespeare's
most ironic play, Troilus and Cressida, presents in Ulysses the
voice of worldly wisdom, expounding with great eloquence the two primary
categories of the perspective of tragic irony in the fallen world, time and the
hierarchic chain of being. The extraordinary treatment of the tragic vision of
time by Nietzsche's Zarathustra, in which the heroic acceptance of cyclical
return becomes a glumly cheerful acceptance of a cosmology of identical
recurrence, marks the influence of an age of irony.
Anyone accustomed to think archetypally of literature will recognize in
tragedy a mimesis of sacrifice. Tragedy is a paradoxical combination of a
fearful sense of Tightness (the hero must fall) and a pitying sense of
wrongness (it is too bad that he falls). There is a similar paradox in the two
elements of sacrifice. One of these is communion, the dividing of a heroic or
divine body among a group which brings them into unity with, and as, that body.
The other is propitiation, the sense that in spite of the communion the body
really belongs to another, a greater, and a potentially wrathful power. The
ritual analogies to tragedy are more obvious than the psychological ones, for
it is irony, not tragedy, that represents the nightmare or anxiety-dream. But,
just as the literary critic finds Freud most suggestive for the theory of
comedy, and Jung for the theory of romance, so for the theory of tragedy one
naturally looks to the psychology of the will to power, as expounded in Adler
and Nietzsche. Here one finds a "Dionysiac" aggressive will,
intoxicated by dreams of its own omnipotence, impinging upon an [214] "Apollonian"
sense of external and immovable order. As a mimesis of ritual, the tragic hero
is not really killed or eaten, but the corresponding thing in art still takes
place, a vision of death which draws the survivors into a new unity. As a
mimesis of dream, the inscrutable tragic hero, like the proud and silent swan,
becomes articulate at the point of death, and the audience, like the poet in
Kubla Khan, revives his song within itself. With his fall, a greater world
beyond which his gigantic spirit had blocked out becomes for an instant
visible, but there is also a sense of the mystery and remoteness of that world.
If we are right in our suggestion that romance, tragedy, irony and
comedy are all episodes in a total quest-myth, we can see how it is that comedy
can contain a potential tragedy within itself. In myth, the hero is a god, and
hence he does not die, but dies and rises again. The ritual pattern behind the
catharsis of comedy is the resurrection that follows the death, the epiphany or
manifestation of the risen hero. In Aristophanes the hero, who often goes
through a point of ritual death, is treated as a risen god, hailed as a new
Zeus, or given the quasi-divine honors of the Olympic victor. In New Comedy the
new human body is both a hero and a social group. The Aeschylean trilogy
proceeds to the comic satyr-play, which is said to have affinities with spring
festivals. Christianity, too, sees tragedy as an episode in the divine comedy,
the larger scheme of redemption and resurrection. The sense of tragedy as a prelude
to comedy seems almost inseparable from anything explicitly Christian. The
serenity of the final double chorus in the St. Matthew Passion would hardly be
attainable if composer and audience did not know that there was more to the
story. Nor would the death of Samson lead to "calm of mind, all passion
spent," if Samson were not a prototype of the rising Christ, associated at
the appropriate moment with the phoenix.
This is an example of the way in which myths explain the structural
principles behind familiar literary facts, in this case the fact that to make a
sombre action end happily is easy enough, and to reverse the procedure almost
impossible. (Of course we have a natural dislike of seeing pleasant situations
turn out disastrously, but if a poet is working on a solid structural basis,
our natural likes and dislikes have nothing to do with the matter.) Even
Shakespeare, who can do anything, never does quite this. The action of King
Lear, which seems heading for some kind of serenity, is suddenly [215] wrenched
into agony by the hanging of Cordelia, providing a conclusion which the stage
refused to act for over a century, but none of Shakespeare's tragedies
impresses us as a comedy gone wrong -- Romeo and Juliet has a suggestion of
such a structure, but it is only a suggestion. Hence while of course a tragedy
may contain a comic action, it contains it only episodically as a subordinate
contrast or underplot.
The characterization of tragedy is very like that of comedy in reverse.
The source of nemesis, whatever it is, is an eiron, and may appear in a great
variety of agents, from wrathful gods to hypocritical villains. In comedy we
noticed three main types of eiron characters: a benevolent withdrawing and
returning figure, the tricky slave or vice, and the hero and heroine. We have
the tragic counterpart to the withdrawn eiron in the god who decrees the tragic
action, like Athene in Ajax or Aphrodite in Hippolytus; a Christian example is
God the Father in Paradise Lost. He may also be a ghost, like Hamlet's father;
or it may not be a person at all but simply an invisible force known only by
its effects, like the death that quietly seizes on Tamburlaine when the time
has come for him to die. Often, as in the revenge-tragedy, it is an event
previous to the action of which the tragedy itself is the consequence.
A tragic counterpart to the vice or tricky slave may be discerned in the
soothsayer or prophet who foresees the inevitable end, or more of it than the
hero does, like Teiresias. A closer example is the Machiavellian villain of
Elizabethan drama, who, like the vice in comedy, is a convenient catalyzer of
the action because he requires the minimum of motivation, being a self-starting
principle of malevolence. Like the comic vice, too, he is something of an
architectus or projection of the author's will, in this case for a tragic
conclusion. "I limned this night-piece," says Webster's Lodovico,
"and it was my best." Iago dominates the action of Othello almost to
the point of being a tragic counterpart to the black king or evil magician of
romance. The affinities of the Machiavellian villain with the diabolical are
naturally close, and he may be an actual devil like Mephistopheles, but the
sense of awfulness belonging to an agent of catastrophe can also make him
something more like the high priest of a sacrifice. There is a touch of this in
Webster's Bosola. King Lear has a Machiavellian villain in Edmund, and Edmund
is contrasted with Edgar. Edgar, with his bewildering variety [216] of
disguises, his appearance to blind or mad people in different roles, and his
tendency to appear on the third sound of the trumpet and to come pat like the
catastrophe of the old comedy, seems to be an experiment in a new type, a kind
of tragic "virtue," if I may coin this word by analogy, a counterpart
in the order of nature to a guardian angel or similar attendant in romance.
The tragic hero usually belongs of course to the alazon group, an
impostor in the sense that he is self-deceived or made dizzy by hubris. In many
tragedies he begins as a semi-divine figure, at least in his own eyes, and then
an inexorable dialectic sets to work which separates the divine pretence from
the human actuality. 'They told me I was everything," says Lear: "
'tis a lie; I am not ague-proof." The tragic hero is usually vested with
supreme authority, but is often in the more ambiguous position of a tyrannos
whose rule depends on his own abilities, rather than a purely hereditary or de
jure monarch (basileus) like Duncan. The latter is more directly a symbol of
the original vision or birthright, and is often a somewhat pathetic victim,
like Richard II, or even Agamemnon. Parental figures in tragedy have the same
ambivalence that they have in all other forms.
We found in comedy that the term bomolochos or buffoon need not be
restricted to farce, but could be extended to cover comic characters who are
primarily entertainers, with the function of in creasing or focussing the comic
mood. The corresponding contrasting type in tragedy is the suppliant, the
character, often female, who presents a picture of unmitigated helplessness and
destitution. Such a figure is pathetic, and pathos, though it seems a gentler
and more relaxed mood than tragedy, is even more terrifying. Its basis is the
exclusion of an individual from a group, hence it attacks the deepest fear in
ourselves that we possess a fear much deeper than the relatively cosy and
sociable bogey of hell. In the figure of the suppliant pity and terror are
brought to the highest possible pitch of intensity, and the awful consequences
of rejecting the suppliant for all concerned is a central theme of Greek
tragedy. Suppliant figures are often women threatened with death or rape, or
children, like Prince Arthur in King John. The fragility of Shakespeare's Ophelia
marks an affinity with the suppliant type. Often, too, the suppliant is in the
structurally tragic position of having lost a place of greatness: this is the
position of Adam and Eve in the tenth book of Paradise Lost, of the Trojan
women after the fall [217] of Troy, of Oedipus in the Colonus play, and so on.
A subordinate figure who plays the role of focussing the tragic mood is the
messenger who regularly announces the catastrophe in Greek tragedy. In the
final scene of comedy, when the author is usually trying to get all his
characters on the stage at once, we often notice the introduction of a new
character, generally a messenger bearing some missing piece of the cognitio,
such as Jaques de Boys in As You Like It or the gentle astringer in All's Well,
who represents the comic counterpart.
Finally, a tragic counterpart of the comic refuser of festivity may be
discerned in a tragic type of plain dealer who may be simply the faithful
friend of the hero, like Horatio in Hamlet, but is often an outspoken critic of
the tragic action, like Kent in King Lear or Enobarbus in Antony and Cleopatra.
Such a character is in the position of refusing, or at any rate resisting, the
tragic movement toward catastrophe. Abdiel's role in the tragedy of Satan in
Paradise Lost is similar. The familiar figures of Cassandra and Teiresias
combine this role with that of the soothsayer. Such figures, when they occur in
a tragedy without a chorus, are often called chorus characters, as they
illustrate one of the essential functions of the tragic chorus. In comedy a
society forms around the hero: in tragedy the chorus, however faithful, usually
represents the society from which the hero is gradually isolated. Hence what it
expresses is a social norm against which the hero's hubris may be measured The
chorus is not the voice of the hero's conscience by any means, but very seldom
does it encourage him in his hubris or prompt him to disastrous action. The
chorus or chorus character is, so to speak, the embryonic germ of comedy in tragedy,
just as the refuser of festivity, the melancholy Jaques or Alceste, is a tragic
germ in comedy.
In comedy the erotic and social affinities of the hero are combined and
unified in the final scene; tragedy usually makes love and the social structure
irreconcilable and contending forces, a conflict which reduces love to passion
and social activity to a forbidding and imperative duty. Comedy is much
concerned with integrating the family and adjusting the family to society as a
whole; tragedy is much concerned with breaking up the family and opposing it to
the rest of society. This gives us the tragic archetype of Antigone, of which
the conflict of love and honor in Classical French drama, of Neigung and Pflicht in
Schiller, of passion and [218] authority in the Jacobeans, are all moralized
simplifications. Again, just as the heroine of comedy often ties together the
action, so it is obvious that the central female figure of a tragic action will
often polarize the tragic conflict. Eve, Helen, Gertrude, and Emily in
the Knight's Tale are some ready instances: the structural
role of Briseis in theIliad is similar. Comedy works out the proper
relations of its characters and prevents heroes from marrying their sisters or
mothers; tragedy presents the disaster of Oedipus or the incest of Siegmund.
There is a great deal in tragedy about pride of race and birthright, but its
general tendency is to isolate a ruling or noble family from the rest of
society.
The phases of tragedy move from the heroic to the ironic, the first
three corresponding to the first three phases of romance, the last three to the
last three of irony. The first phase of tragedy is the one in which the central
character is given the greatest possible dignity in contrast to the other
characters, so that we get the perspective of a stag pulled down by wolves. The
sources of dignity are courage and innocence, and in this phase the hero or
heroine usually is innocent. This phase corresponds to the myth of the birth of
the hero in romance, a theme which is occasionally incorporated into a tragic
structure, as in Racine's Athalie. But owing to the unusual
difficulty of making an interesting dramatic character out of an infant, the
central and typical figure of this phase is the calumniated woman, often a
mother the legitimacy of whose child is suspected. A whole series of tragedies
based on a Griselda figure belong here, stretching from the Senecan Octavia to
Hardy's Tess, and including the tragedy of Hermione in The
Winter's Tale. If we are to read Alcestis as a tragedy, we
have to see it as a tragedy of this phase in which Alcestis is violated by
Death and then has her fidelity vindicated by being restored to life. Cymbeline belongs
here too: in this play the theme of the birth of the hero appears offstage, for
Cymbeline was the king of Britain at the time of the birth of Christ, and the
halcyon peace in which the play concludes has a suppressed reference to this.
An even clearer example, ,and certainly one of the greatest in English
literature, is The Duchess of Malfi. The Duchess has the innocence
of abundant life in a sick and melancholy society, where the fact that she has
"youth and a little beauty" is precisely why she is hated. She
reminds us too that one of the essential characteristics [219] of innocence in
the martyr is an unwillingness to die. When Bosola comes to murder her he makes
elaborate attempts to put her half in love with easeful death and to suggest
that death is really a deliverance. The attempt is motivated by a grimly
controlled pity, and is roughly the equivalent of the vinegar sponge in the
Passion. When the Duchess, her back to the wall, says "I am the Duchess of
Malfi still," "still" having its full weight of
"always," we understand how it is that even after her death her
invisible presence continues to be the most vital character in the play. The
White Devil is an ironic parody-treatment of the same phase.
The second phase corresponds to the youth of the romantic hero, and is
in one way or another the tragedy of innocence in the sense of inexperience,
usually involving young people. It may be simply the tragedy of a youthful life
cut off, as in the stories of Iphigeneia and Jephthah's daughter, of Romeo and
Juliet, or, in a more complex situation, in the bewildered mixture of idealism
and priggishness that brings Hippolytus to disaster. The simplicity of Shaw's
Joan and her lack of worldly wisdom place her here also. For us however the
phase is dominated by the archetypal tragedy of the green and golden world, the
loss of the innocence of Adam and Eve, who, no matter how heavy a doctrinal
load they have to carry, will always remain dramatically in the position of
children baffled by their first contact with an adult situation. In many
tragedies of this type the central character survives, so that the action
closes with some adjustment to a new and more mature experience,
"Henceforth I learn that to obey is best," says Adam, as he and Eve
go hand in hand out to the world before them. A less clear cut but similar
resolution occurs when Philoctetes, whose serpent-wound reminds us a little of
Adam, is taken off his island to enter the Trojan war. Ibsen'sLittle Eyolf is
a tragedy of this phase, and with the same continuing conclusion, in which it
is the older characters who are educated through the death of a child.
The third phase, corresponding to the central quest-theme of romance, is
tragedy in which a strong emphasis is thrown on the success or completeness of
the hero's achievement. The Passion belongs here, as do all tragedies in which
the hero is in any way related to or a prototype of Christ, like Samson
Agonistes. The paradox of victory within tragedy may be expressed by a
double perspective in the action. Samson is a buffoon of a Philistine carnival
and simultaneously a tragic hero to the Israelites, but the tragedy [220] ends
in triumph and the carnival in catastrophe. Much the same is true of the mocked
Christ in the Passion. But just as the second phase often ends in anticipation
of greater maturity, so this one is often a sequel to a previous tragic or
heroic action, and comes at the end of a heroic life. One of the greatest
dramatic examples is Oedipus at Colonus, where we find the usual
binary form of a tragedy conditioned by a previous tragic act, ending this time
not in a second disaster, but in a full rich serenity that goes far beyond a
mere resignation to Fate. In narrative literature we may cite Beowulf's last
fight with the dragon, the pendant to his Grendel quest. Shakespeare's Henry
V is a successfully completed romantic quest made tragic by its
implicit context: everybody knows that King Henry died almost immediately and
that sixty years of un broken disaster followed for England -- at least, if
anyone in Shakespeare's audience did not know that, his ignorance was certainly
no fault of Shakespeare's.
The fourth phase is the typical fall of the hero through hubris and
hamartia that we have already discussed. In this phase we cross the boundary
line from innocence to experience, which is also the direction in which the
hero falls. In the fifth phase the ironic element increases, the heroic
decreases, and the characters look further away and in a smaller
perspective. Timon of Athens impresses us as more ironic and
less heroic than the better known tragedies, not simply because Timon is a more
middle-class hero who has to buy what authority he has, but because the feeling
that Timon's suicide has somehow failed to make a fully heroic point is very
strong. Timon is oddly isolated from the final action, in which the breach between
Alcibiades and the Athenians closes up over his head, in striking contrast with
the conclusions of most of the other tragedies, where nobody is allowed to
steal the show from the central character.
The ironic perspective in tragedy is attained by putting the characters
in a state of lower freedom than the audience. For a Christian audience an Old
Testament or pagan setting is ironic in this sense, as it shows its characters
moving according to the conditions of a law, whether Jewish or natural, from
which the audience has been, at least theoretically, redeemed. Samson
Agonistes, though unique in English literature, presents a combination of
Classical form and Hebrew subject-matter that the greatest contemporary
tragedian, Racine, also reached at the end of his life inAthalie and [221] Esther.
Similarly the epilogue to Chaucer's Troilus puts a Courtly
Love tragedy into its historical relation to "payens corsed olde
rites." The events in Geoffrey of Monmouth's British history are supposed
to be contemporary with those of the Old Testament, and the sense of life under
the law is present everywhere in King Lear. The same structural
principle accounts for the use of astrology and other fatalistic machinery
connected with the turning wheels of fate or fortune. Romeo and Juliet are
star-crossed, and Troilus loses Criseyde because every five hundred years
Jupiter and Saturn meet the crescent moon in Cancer and claim another victim.
The tragic action of the fifth phase presents for the most part the tragedy of lost
direction and lack of knowledge, not unlike the second phase except that the
context is the world of adult experience. Oedipus Tyrannus belongs
here, and all tragedies and tragic episodes which suggest the existential
projection of fatalism, and, like much of the Book of Job, seem to raise
metaphysical or theological questions rather than social or moral ones.
Oedipus Tyrannus, however, is already moving into the sixth phase of
tragedy, a world of shock and horror in which the central images are images
of sparagmos, that is, cannibalism, mutilation, and torture. The specific
reaction known as shock is appropriate to a situation of cruelty or outrage.
(The secondary or false shock produced by the outrage done to some emotional
attachment or fixation, as in the critical reception ofJude the
Obscure or Ulysses, has no status in criticism, as false shock is a
disguised resistance to the autonomy of culture.) Any tragedy may have one or
more shocking scenes in it, but sixth-phase tragedy shocks as a whole, in its
total effect. This phase is more common as a subordinate aspect of tragedy than
as its main theme, as unqualified horror or despair makes a difficult
cadence. Prometheus Bound is a tragedy of this phase, though this is
partly an illusion due to its isolation from the trilogy to which it belongs.
In such tragedies the hero is in too great agony or humiliation to gain the
privilege of a heroic pose, hence it is usually easier to make him a villainous
hero, like Marlowe's Barabas, although Faustus also belongs to the same phase.
Seneca is fond of this phase, and bequeathed to the Elizabethans an interest in
the gruesome, an effect which usually has some connection with mutilation, as
when Ferdinand offers to shake hands with the Duchess of Malfi and gives her a
dead man's hand. Titus Andronicus is an experiment in Senecan
sixth-phase horror which [222] makes a great deal of mutilation, and shows also
a strong interest, from the opening scene on, in the sacrificial symbolism of
tragedy. At the end of this phase we reach a point of demonic epiphany, where
we see or glimpse the undisplaced demonic vision, the vision of
the Inferno. Its chief symbols, besides the prison and the mad house, are
the instruments of a torturing death, the cross under the sunset being the
antithesis of the tower under the moon. A strong element of demonic ritual in
public punishments and similar mob amusements is exploited by tragic and ironic
myth. Breaking on the wheel becomes Lear's wheel of fire; bear-baiting is an
image for Gloucester and Macbeth, and for the crucified Prometheus the
humiliation of exposure, the horror of being watched, is a greater misery than
the pain. Derkou theama (behold the spectacle; get your staring over
with) is his bitterest cry. The inability of Milton's blind Samson to stare
back is his greatest torment, and one which forces him to scream at Delilah, in
one of the most terrible passages of all tragic drama, that he will tear her to
pieces if she touches him.
We come now to the mythical
patterns of experience, the attempts to give form to the shifting ambiguities
and complexities of unidealized existence. We cannot find these patterns merely
in the mimetic or representational aspect of such literature, for that aspect
is one of content and not form. As structure, the central principle of ironic
myth is best approached as a parody of romance: the application of romantic
mythical forms to a more realistic content which fits them in unexpected ways.
No one in a romance, Don Quixote protests, ever asks who pays for the hero's
accommodation.
The chief distinction between irony and satire is that satire is
militant irony: its moral norms are relatively clear, and it assumes standards
against which the grotesque and absurd are measured. Sheer invective or
name-calling ("flyting") is satire in which there is relatively
little irony: on the other hand, whenever a reader is not sure what the author's
attitude is or what his own is supposed to be, we have irony with relatively
little satire. Fielding's Jonathan Wild is satiric irony:
certain flat moral judgements made by the narrator (as in the description of
Bagshot in chapter twelve) are in accord with the decorum of the work, but
would be out of key in, [223] say, Madame Bovary. Irony is
consistent both with complete realism of content and with the suppression of
attitude on the part of the author. Satire demands at least a token fantasy, a
content which the reader recognizes as grotesque, and at least an implicit
moral standard, the latter being essential in a militant attitude to
experience. Some phenomena, such as the ravages of disease, may be called
grotesque, but to make fun of them would not be very effective satire. The
satirist has to select his absurdities, and the act of selection is a moral
act.
The argument of Swift's Modest Proposal has a
brain-softening plausibility about it: one is almost led to feel that the
narrator is not only reasonable but even humane; yet the "almost" can
never drop out of any sane man's reaction, and as long as it remains there the
modest proposal will be both fantastic and immoral. When in another passage
Swift suddenly says, discussing the poverty of Ireland, "But my Heart is
too heavy to continue this Irony longer," he is speaking of satire, which
breaks down when its content is too oppressively real to permit the maintaining
of the fantastic or hypothetical tone. Hence satire is irony which is
structurally close to the comic: the comic struggle of two societies, one
normal and the other absurd, is reflected in its double focus of morality and
fantasy. Irony with little satire is the non-heroic residue of tragedy,
centering on a theme of puzzled defeat.
Two things, then, are essential to satire; one is wit or humor founded
on fantasy or a sense of the grotesque or absurd, the other is an object of
attack. Attack without humor, or pure denunciation, forms one of the boundaries
of satire. It is a very hazy boundary, because invective is one of the most
readable forms of literary art, just as panegyric is one of the dullest. It is
an established datum of literature that we like hearing people cursed and are
bored with hearing them praised, and almost any denunciation, if vigorous
enough, is followed by a reader with the kind of pleasure that soon breaks into
a smile. To attack anything, writer and audience must agree on its
undesirability, which means that the content of a great deal of satire founded
on national hatreds, snobbery, prejudice, and personal pique goes out of date
very quickly.
But attack in literature can never be a pure expression of merely
personal or even social hatred, whatever the motivation for it may be, because
the words for expressing hatred, as distinct from enmity, have too limited a
range. About the only ones we have are [224] derived from the animal world, but
calling a man a swine or a skunk or a woman a bitch affords a severely
restricted satisfaction, as most of the unpleasant qualities of the animal are
human projections. As Shakespeare's Thersites says of Menelaus, "to what
form, but that he is, should wit larded with malice, and malice forced with
wit, turn him to? To an ass, were nothing; he is both ass and ox; to an ox,
were nothing; he is both ox and ass." For effective attack we must reach
some kind of impersonal level, and that commits the attacker, if only by
implication, to a moral standard. The satirist commonly takes a high moral
line. Pope asserts that he is "To Virtue only and her friends a
friend," suggesting that that is what he is really being when he is
reflecting on the cleanliness of the underwear worn by the lady who had jilted
him.
Humor, like attack, is founded on convention. The world of humor is a
rigidly-stylized world in which generous Scotchmen, obedient wives, beloved
mothers-in-law, and professors with presence of mind are not permitted to
exist. All humor demands agreement that certain things, such as a picture of a
wife beating her husband in a comic strip, are conventionally funny. To
introduce a comic strip in which a husband beats his wife would distress the
reader, because it would mean learning a new convention. The humor of pure
fantasy, the other boundary of satire, belongs to romance, though it is uneasy
there, as humor perceives the incongruous, and the conventions of romance are
idealized. Most fantasy is pulled back into satire by a powerful undertow often
called allegory, which may be described as the implicit reference to experience
in the perception of the incongruous. The White Knight in Alice who felt that
one should be provided for everything, and therefore put anklets around his
horse's feet to guard against the bites of sharks, may pass as pure fantasy.
But when he goes on to sing an elaborate parody of Wordsworth we begin to sniff
the acrid, pungent smell of satire, and when we take a second look at the White
Knight we recognize a character type closely related both to Quixote and to the
pedant of comedy.
As in this mythos we have the difficulty of two words
to contend with, it may be simplest, if the reader is now accustomed to our
sequence of six phases, to start with them and describe them in order, instead
of abstracting a typical form and discussing it first. The first three are
phases of satire, and correspond to the first three or ironic phases of comedy.
[225]
The first phase corresponds to the first phase of ironic comedy in which
there is no displacement of the humorous society. The sense of absurdity about
such a comedy arises as a kind of back fire or recall after the work has been
seen or read. Once we have finished with it, deserts of futility open up on all
sides, and we have, in spite of the humor, a sense of nightmare and a close
proximity to something demonic. Even in very light-hearted comedy we may get a
trace of this feeling: if the main theme of Pride and Prejudice had
been the married life of Collins and Charlotte Lucas, one wonders how long
Collins would continue to be funny. Hence it is in decorum for even a satire
prevailingly light in tone, such as Pope's second Moral Essay on the characters
of women, to rise to a terrifying climax of moral intensity.
The satire typical of this phase may be called the satire of the low
norm. It takes for granted a world which is full of anomalies, injustices,
follies, and crimes, and yet is permanent and undisplaceable. Its principle is
that anyone who wishes to keep his balance in such a world must learn first of
all to keep his eyes open and his mouth shut. Counsels of prudence, urging the
reader in effect to adopt an eiron role, have been prominent
in literature from Egyptian times. What is recommended is conventional life at
its best: a clairvoyant knowledge of human nature in oneself and others, an
avoidance of all illusion and compulsive behavior, a reliance on observation
and timing rather than on aggressiveness. This is wisdom, the tried and tested
way of life, which does not question the logic of social convention, but merely
follows the procedures which in fact do serve to maintain one's balance from
one day to the next. The eiron of the low norm takes an
attitude of flexible pragmatism; he assumes that society will, if given any
chance, behave more or less like Caliban's Setebos in Browning's poem, and he
conducts himself accordingly. On all doubtful points of behavior convention is
his deepest conviction. And however good or bad expertly conventional behavior
may be thought to be, it is certainly the most difficult of all forms of
behavior to satirize, just as anyone with a new theory of behavior, even if
saint or prophet, is the easiest of all people to ridicule as a crank.
Hence the satirist may employ a plain, common-sense, conventional person
as a foil for the various alazons of society. Such a person
may be the author himself or a narrator, and he corresponds to the plain dealer
in comedy or the blunt adviser in tragedy. When [226] distinguished from the
author, he is often a rustic with pastoral affinities, illustrating the
connection of his role with the agroikos type in comedy. The
kind of American satire that passes as folk humor, exemplified by the Biglow
Papers, Mr. Dooley, Artemus Ward, and Will Rogers, makes a good deal of him,
and this genre is closely linked with the North American development of the
counsel of prudence in Poor Richard's Almanac and the Sam Slick papers. Other
examples are easy enough to find, both where we expect them, as in Crabbe,
whose tale The Patron also belongs to the counsel-of-prudence
genre, and where we might not expect them, as in the Fish-Eater dialogue in
Erasmus's Colloquies, Chaucer represents himself as a shy, demure,
inconspicuous member of his pilgrimage, agreeing politely with everybody
("And I seyde his opinion was good"), and showing to the pilgrims
none of the powers of observation that he displays to his reader. We are not
surprised therefore to find that one of his "own" tales is in the
counsel of prudence tradition.
The most elaborate form of low-norm satire is the encyclopaedic form
favored by the Middle Ages, closely allied to preaching, and generally based on
the encyclopaedic scheme of the seven deadly sins, a form which survived as
late as Elizabethan times in Nashe's Pierce Penilesse and
Lodge's Wits Miserie. Erasmus's Praise of Folly belongs
to this tradition, in which the link with the corresponding comic phase, the
view of an upside-down world dominated by humors and ruling passions, can be
clearly seen. When adopted by a preacher, or even an intellectual, the low norm
device is part of an implied a fortiori argument: if people
cannot reach even ordinary common sense, or church porch virtue, there is
little point in comparing them with any higher standards.
Where gaiety predominates in such satire, we have an attitude which
fundamentally accepts social conventions but stresses tolerance and flexibility
within their limits. Close to the conventional norm we find the lovable
eccentric, the Uncle Toby or Betsey Trotwood who diversifies, without
challenging, accepted codes of behavior. Such characters have much of the child
about them, and a child's behavior is usually thought of as coming towards an
accepted standard instead of moving away from it. Where attack predominates, we
have an inconspicuous, unobtrusiveeiron standard contrasted with
the alazons or blocking humors who are in charge of society.
This situation has for its archetype an ironic [227] counterpart of the romance
theme of giant-killing. For society to exist at all there must be a delegation
of prestige and influence to organized groups such as the church, the army, the
professions and the government, all of which consist of individuals given more
than individual power by the institutions to which they belong. If a satirist
presents, say, a clergyman as a fool or hypocrite, he is, qua satirist,
attacking neither a man nor a church. The former has no literary or
hypothetical point, and the latter carries him outside the range of satire. He
is attacking an evil man protected by his church, and such a man is a gigantic
monster: monstrous because not what he should be, gigantic because protected by
his position and by the prestige of good clergymen. The cowl might make the
monk if it were not for satire.
Milton says, "for a Satyr as it was born out of a Tragedy, so ought
to resemble his parentage, to strike high, and adventure dangerously at the
most eminent vices among the greatest persons." Apart from the etymology,
this needs one qualification: a great vice does not need a great person to
represent it. We have mentioned the gigantic size of Sir Epicure Mammon's dream
in The Alchemist: the whole mystery of the corrupted human will is
in it, yet the utter impotence of the dreamer is essential to the satire.
Similarly, we miss much of the point of Jonathan Wild unless
we take the hero seriously as a parody of greatness, or false social standards
of valuation. But in general the principle may be accepted for the satirist's
antagonists that the larger they come, the easier they fall. In low-norm satire
the alazon is a Goliath encountered by a tiny David with his
sudden and vicious stones, a giant prodded by a cool and observant but almost
invisible enemy into a blind, stampeding fury and then polished off at leisure.
This situation has run through satire from the stories of Polyphemus and
Blunderbore to, in a much more ironic and equivocal context, the Chaplin films.
Dryden transforms his victims into fantastic dinosaurs of bulging flesh and
peanut brains; he seems genuinely impressed by the "goodly and great"
bulk of Og and by the furious energy of the poet Doeg.
The figure of the low-norm eiron is irony's substitute
for the hero, and when he is removed from satire we can see more clearly that
one of the central themes of the mythos is the disappearance
of the heroic. This is the main reason for the predominance in fictional satire
of what may be called the Omphale archetype, the man bullied or dominated by
women, which has been prominent in [228] satire all through its history, and
embraces a vast area of contemporary humor, both popular and sophisticated.
Similarly, when the giant or monster is removed we can see that he is the
mythical form of society, the hydra or fama full of tongues, Spenser's blatant
beast which is still at large. And while the crank with his new idea is an
obvious target for satire, still social convention is mainly fossilized dogma,
and the standard appealed to by low-norm satire is a set of conventions largely
invented by dead cranks. The strength of the conventional person is not in the
conventions but in his common-sense way of handling them. Hence the logic of
satire itself drives it on from its first phase of conventional satire on the
unconventional to a second phase in which the sources and values of conventions
themselves are objects of ridicule.
The simplest form of the corresponding second phase of comedy is the
comedy of escape, in which a hero runs away to a more congenial society without
transforming his own. The satiric counter part of this is the picaresque novel,
the story of the successful rogue who, from Reynard the Fox on, makes
conventional society look foolish without setting up any positive standard. The
picaresque novel is the social form of what with Don Quixote modulates into a
more intellectualized satire, the nature of which needs some explanation.
Satire, according to Juvenal's useful if hackneyed formula, has an
interest in anything men do. The philosopher, on the other hand, teaches a
certain way or method of living; he stresses some things and despises others;
what he recommends is carefully selected from the data of human life; he
continually passes moral judgements on social behavior. His attitude is
dogmatic; that of the satirist pragmatic. Hence satire may often represent the
collision between a selection of standards from experience and the feeling that
experience is bigger than any set of beliefs about it. The satirist
demonstrates the infinite variety of what men do by showing the futility, not
only of saying what they ought to do, but even of attempts to systematize or
formulate a coherent scheme of what they do. Philosophies of life abstract from
life, and an abstraction implies the leaving out of inconvenient data. The
satirist brings up these in convenient data, sometimes in the form of
alternative and equally plausible theories, like the Erewhonian treatment of
crime and disease or Swift's demonstration of the mechanical operation of
spirit. [229]
The central theme in the second or quixotic phase of satire, then, is
the setting of ideas and generalizations and theories and dogmas over against
the life they are supposed to explain. This theme is presented very clearly in
Lucian's dialogue The Sale of Lives, in which a series of
slave-philosophers pass in review, with all their arguments and guarantees,
before a buyer who has to consider living with them. He buys a few, it is true,
but as slaves, not as masters or teachers. Lucian's attitude to Greek
philosophy is repeated in the attitude of Erasmus and Rabelais to the
scholastics, of Swift and Samuel Butler I to Descartes and the Royal Society,
of Voltaire to the Leibnitzians, of Peacock to the Romantics, of Samuel Butler
II to the Darwinians, of Aldous Huxley to the behaviorists. We notice that
low-norm satire often becomes merely anti-intellectual, a tendency that crops
up in Crabbe (vide The Learned Boy) and even in Swift. The influence of
low-norm satire in American culture has produced a popular contempt for
longhairs and ivory towers, an example of what may be called a fallacy of
poetic projection, or taking literary conventions to be facts of life.
Anti-intellectual satire proper, however, is based on a sense of the
comparative naivete of systematic thought, and should not be limited by such
ready-made terms as skeptical or cynical.
Skepticism itself may be or become a dogmatic attitude, a comic humor of
doubting plain evidence. Cynicism is a little closer to the satiric norm:
Menippus, the founder of the Menippean satire, was a cynic, and cynics are
generally associated with the role of intellectual Thersites. Lyly's play Campaspe,
for instance, presents Plato, Aristotle, and Diogenes, but the first two are
bores, and Diogenes, who is not a philosopher at all but an Elizabethan clown
of the malcontent type, steals the show. But still cynicism is a philosophy,
and one that may produce the strange spiritual pride of the Peregrinus of whom
Lucian makes a searching and terrible analysis. In the Sale of Lives the
cynic and the skeptic are auctioned in their turn, and the latter is the last
to be sold, dragged off to have his very skepticism refuted, not by argument
but by life. Erasmus and Burton called themselves Democritus Junior, followers
of the philosopher who laughed at mankind, but Lucian's buyer considers that
Democritus too has overdone his pose. Insofar as the satirist has a "position"
of his own, it is the preference of practice to theory, experience to
metaphysics. When Lucian goes to consult his master Menippus, he is told that
the method of wisdom is to do the task [230] that lies to hand, advice repeated
in Voltaire's Candide and in the instructions given to the
unborn in Erewhon. Thus philosophical pedantry becomes, as every
target of satire eventually does, a form of romanticism or the imposing of
over-simplified ideals on experience.
The satiric attitude here is neither philosophical nor
anti-philosophical, but an expression of the hypothetical form of art. Satire
on ideas is only the special kind of art that defends its own creative
detachment. The demand for order in thought produces a supply of intellectual
systems: some of these attract and convert artists, but as an equally great
poet could defend any other system equally well, no one system can contain the
arts as they stand. Hence a systematic reasoner, given the power, would be
likely to establish hierarchies in the arts, or censor and expurgate as Plato
wished to do to Homer. Satire on systems of reasoning, especially on the social
effects of such systems, is art's first line of defence against all such
invasions.
In the warfare of science against superstition, the satirists have done
famously. Satire itself appears to have begun with the Greek silloi which
were pro-scientific attacks on superstition. In English literature, Chaucer and
Ben Jonson riddled the alchemists with a cross-fire of their own jargon; Nashe
and Swift hounded astrologers into premature graves; Browning's Sludge
the Medium annihilated the spiritualists, and a rabble of occultists,
numerologists, Pythagoreans, and Rosicrucians lie sprawling in the wake
of Hudibras. To the scientist it may seem little short of perverse
that satire placidly goes on making fun of legitimate astronomers in The
Elephant in the Moon, of experimental laboratories inGulliver's Travels,
of Darwinian and Malthusian cosmology in Erewhon, of conditioned
reflexes in Brave New World, of technological efficiency in 1984.
Charles Fort, one of the few who have continued the tradition of intellectual
satire in this century, brings the wheel full circle by mocking the scientists
for their very freedom from superstition itself, a rational attitude which,
like all rational attitudes, still refuses to examine all the evidence.
Similarly with religion. The satirist may feel with Lucian that the
eliminating of superstition would also eliminate religion, or with Erasmus that
it would restore health to religion. But whether Zeus exists or not is a
question; that men who think him vicious and stupid will insist that he change
the weather is a fact, accepted by [231] scoffer and devout alike. Any really
devout person would surely welcome a satirist who cauterized hypocrisy and
superstition as an ally of true religion. Yet once a hypocrite who sounds
exactly like a good man is sufficiently blackened, the good man also may begin
to seem a little dingier than he was. Those who would agree even with the
theoretical parts of Holy Willie's Prayer in Burns look rather
like Holy Willies themselves. One feels similarly that while the personal
attitudes of Erasmus, Rabelais, Swift, and Voltaire to institutional religion
varied a good deal, the effect of their satire varies much less. Satire on
religion includes the parody of the sacramental life in English Protestantism
that runs from Milton's divorce pamphlets to The Way of All Flesh,
and the antagonism to Christianity in Nietzsche, Yeats, and D. H. Lawrence
based on the conception of Jesus as another kind of romantic idealist.
The narrator in Erewhon remarks that while the real
religion of most of the Erewhonians was, whatever they said it was, the
acceptance of low-norm conventionality (the goddess Ydgrun), there was also a
small group of "high Ydgrunites" who were the best people he found in
Erewhon. The attitude of these people reminds us rather of Montaigne: they had
the eiron's sense of the value of conventions that had been long
established and were now harmless; they had the eiron's distrust of
the ability of anyone's reason, including their own, to transform society into
a better structure. But they were also intellectually detached from the
conventions they lived with, and were capable of seeing their anomalies and
absurdities as well as their stabilizing conservatism.
The literary form that high Ydgrunism produces in second-phase satire we
may call the ingenu form, after Voltaire's dialogue of that
name. Here an outsider to the society, in this case an American Indian, is the
low norm: he has no dogmatic views of his own, but he grants none of the
premises which make the absurdities of society look logical to those accustomed
to them. He is really a pastoral figure, and like the pastoral, a form
congenial to satire, he contrasts a set of simple standards with the complex
rationalizations of society. But we have just seen that it is precisely the
complexity of data in experience which the satirist insists on and the simple
set of standards which he distrusts. That is why theingenu is an
outsider; he comes from another world which is either unattainable or
associated with something else undesirable. Montaigne's cannibals have all the
virtues we have not, if we don't mind being [232] cannibals. More's Utopia is
an ideal state except that to enter it we must give up the idea of Christendom.
The Houyhnhnms live the life of reason and nature better than we, but Gulliver
finds that he is born a Yahoo, and that such a life would be nearer the
capacities of gifted animals than of humans. Whenever the "other
world" appears in satire, it appears as an ironic counterpart to our own,
a reversal of accepted social standards. This form of satire is represented in
Lucian's Kataplous and Charon, journeys to the other
world in which the eminent in this one are shown doing appropriate but
unaccustomed things, a form incorporated in Rabelais, and in the medieval danse
macabre. In the last named the simple equality of death is set against the
complex inequalities of life.
Intellectual satire defends the creative detachment in art, but art too
tends to seek out socially accepted ideas and become in its turn a social
fixation. We have spoken of the idealized art of romance as in particular the
form in which an ascendant class tends to express itself, and so the rising
middle class in medieval Europe naturally turned to mock-romance. Other forms
of satire have a similar function, whether so intended or not. The danse
macabre and the kataplous are ironic reversals of the
kind of romanticism that we have in the serious vision of the other world. In
Dante, for instance, the judgements of the next world usually confirm the
standards of this one, and in heaven itself nearly the whole available
billeting is marked for officers only. The cultural effect of such satire is
not to denigrate romance, but to prevent any group of conventions from
dominating the whole of literary experience. Second-phase satire shows
literature assuming a special function of analysis, of breaking up the lumber
of stereotypes, fossilized beliefs, superstitious terrors, crank theories,
pedantic dogmatisms, oppressive fashions, and all other things that impede the
free movement (not necessarily, of course, the progress) of society. Such
satire is the completion of the logical process known as the reductio
ad absurdum, which is not designed to hold one in perpetual captivity, but
to bring one to the point at which one can escape from an incorrect procedure.
The romantic fixation which revolves around the beauty of perfect form,
in art or elsewhere, is also a logical target for satire. The word satire is
said to come from satura, or hash, and a kind of parody of form
seems to run all through its tradition, from the [233] mixture of prose and
verse in early satire to the jerky cinematic changes of scene in Rabelais (I am
thinking of a somewhat archaic type of cinema). Tristram Shandy andDon
Juan illustrate very clearly the constant tendency to self-parody in
satiric rhetoric which prevents even the process of writing itself from
becoming an over simplified convention or ideal. In Don Juan we
simultaneously read the poem and watch the poet at work writing it: we
eavesdrop on his associations, his struggles for rhymes, his tentative and
discarded plans, the subjective preferences organizing his choice of details
(e.g.: "Her stature tall -- I hate a dumpy woman"), his decisions
whether to be "serious" or mask himself with humor. All of this and
even more is true of Tristram Shandy. A deliberate rambling
digressiveness, which in A Tale of a Tub reaches the point of
including a digression in praise of digressions, is endemic in the narrative
technique of satire, and so is a calculated bathos or art of sinking in its
suspense, such as the quizzical mock-oracular conclusions in Apuleius and
Rabelais and in the refusal of Sterne for hundreds of pages even to get his
hero born. An extraordinary number of great satires are fragmentary,
unfinished, or anonymous. In ironic fiction a good many devices turning on the
difficulty of communication, such as having a story presented through an idiot
mind, serve the same purpose. Virginia Woolf's The Waves is
made up of speeches of characters constructed precisely out of what they do not
say, but what their behavior and attitudes say in spite of them.
This technique of disintegration brings us well into the third phase of
satire, the satire of the high norm. Second-phase satire may make a tactical
defence of the pragmatic against the dogmatic, but here we must let go even of
ordinary common sense as a standard. For common sense too has certain implied
dogmas, notably that the data of sense experience are reliable and consistent,
and that our customary associations with things form a solid basis for
interpreting the present and predicting the future. The satirist cannot explore
all the possibilities of his form without seeing what happens if he questions
these assumptions. That is why he so often gives to ordinary life a logical and
self-consistent shift of perspective. He will show us society suddenly in a
telescope as posturing and dignified pygmies, or in a microscope as hideous and
reeking giants, or he will change his hero into an ass and show us how humanity
looks from an ass's point of view. This type of fantasy [234] breaks down customary
associations, deduces sense experience to one of many possible categories, and
brings out the tentative, als ob basis of all our thinking.
Emerson says that such shifts of perspective afford "a low degree of the
sublime," but actually they afford something of far greater artistic
importance, a high degree of the ridiculous. And, consistently with the general
basis of satire as parody-romance, they are usually adaptations of romance
themes: the fairyland of little people, the land of giants, the world of
enchanted animals, the wonderlands parodied in Lucian's True History.
When we fall back from the outworks of faith and reason to the tangible
realities of the senses, satire follows us up. A slight shift of perspective, a
different tinge in the emotional coloring, and the solid earth becomes an
intolerable horror. Gulliver's Travels shows us man as a
venomous rodent, man as a noisome and clumsy pachyderm, the mind of man as a
bear-pit, and the body of man as a compound of filth and ferocity. But Swift is
simply following where his satiric genius leads him, and genius seems to have
led practically every great satirist to become what the world calls obscene.
Social convention means people parading in front of each other, and the
preservation of it demands that the dignity of some men and the beauty of some
women should be thought of apart from excretion, copulation, and similar
embarrassments. Constant reference to these latter brings us down to a bodily
democracy paralleling the democracy of death in the danse macabre.
Swift's affinity with the danse macabre tradition is marked in
his description of the Struldbrugs, and his Directions to Servants and
his more unquotable poems are in the tradition of the medieval preachers who
painted the repulsiveness of gluttony and lechery. For here as everywhere else
in satire there is a moral reference: it is all very well to eat, drink, and be
merry, but one cannot always put off dying until tomorrow.
In the riotous chaos of Rabelais, Petronius, and Apuleius satire plunges
through to its final victory over common sense. When we have finished with
their weirdly logical fantasies of debauch, dream, and delirium we wake up
wondering if Paracelsus' suggestion is right that the things seen in delirium
are really there, like stars in daytime, and invisible for the same reason.
Lucius becomes initiated and slips evasively out of our grasp, whether he lied
or told the truth, as St. Augustine says with a touch of exasperation; Rabelais
promises us a final oracle and leaves us staring at an empty [235] bottle;
Joyce's HCE struggles for pages toward wakening, but just as we seem on the
point of grasping something tangible we are swung around to the first page of
the book again. The Satyricon is a torn fragment from what
seems like a history of some monstrous Atlantean race that vanished in the sea,
still drunk.
The first phase of satire is dominated by the figure of the
giant-killer, but in this rending of the stable universe a giant power rears up
in satire itself. When the Philistine giant comes out to battle with the
children of light, he naturally expects to find someone his own size ready to
meet him, someone who is head and shoulders over every man in Israel. Such a
Titan would have to bear down his opponent by sheer weight of words, and hence
be a master of that technique of torrential abuse which we call invective. The
gigantic figures in Rabelais, the awakened forms of the bound or sleeping
giants that meet us in Finnegans Wake and the opening of Gullivers
Travels, are expressions of a creative exuberance of which the most typical
and obvious sign is the verbal tempest, the tremendous outpouring of words in
catalogues, abusive epithets and erudite technicalities which since the third
chapter of Isaiah (a satire on female ornament) has been a feature, and almost
a monopoly, of third-phase satire. Its golden age in English literature was the
age of Burton, Nashe, Marston, and Urquhart of Cromarty, the uninhibited
translator of Rabelais, who in his spare time was what Nashe would call a
"scholastical squitter-book," producing books with such titles
as Trissotetras,Pantochronochanon, Exkubalauron and Logopandecteison.
Nobody except Joyce has in modern English made much sustained effort to carry
on this tradition of verbal exuberance: even Carlyle, from this point of view,
is a sad comedown after Burton and Urquhart. In American culture it is
represented by the "tall talk" of the folklore boaster, which has
some literary congeners in the catalogues of Whitman and Moby Dick.
With the fourth phase we move around to the ironic aspect of tragedy,
and satire begins to recede. The fall of the tragic hero, especially in
Shakespeare, is so delicately balanced emotionally that we almost exaggerate
any one element in it merely by calling attention to it. One of these elements
is the elegiac aspect in which irony is at a minimum, the sense of gentle and
dignified pathos, often symbolized by music, which marks the desertion of
Antony by Hercules, the dream of the rejected Queen Catherine in Henry VIII,
Hamlet's "absent thee from felicity awhile," and Othello's [236]
Aleppo speech. One can of course find irony even here, as Mr. Eliot has found
it in the last named, but the main emotional weight is surely thrown on the
opposite side. Yet we are also aware that Hamlet dies in the middle of a
frantically muddled effort at revenge which has taken eight lives instead of
one, that Cleopatra fades away with great dignity after a careful search for
easy ways to die, that Coriolanus is badly confused by his mother and violently
resents being called a boy. Such tragic irony differs from satire in that there
is no attempt to make fun of the character, but only to bring out clearly the
"all too human," as distinct from the heroic, aspects of the tragedy.
King Lear attempts to achieve heroic dignity through his position as a king and
father, and finds it instead in his suffering humanity: hence it is in King
Lear that we find what has been called the "comedy of the
grotesque," the ironic parody of the tragic situation, most elaborately
developed.
As a phase of irony in its own right, the fourth phase looks at tragedy
from below, from the moral and realistic perspective of the state of
experience. It stresses the humanity of its heroes, minimizes the sense of
ritual inevitability in tragedy, supplies social and psychological explanations
for catastrophe, and makes as much as possible of human misery seem, in
Thoreau's phrase, "superfluous and evitable." This is the phase of
most sincere, explicit realism: it is in general Tolstoy's phase, and also that
of a good deal of Hardy and Conrad. One of its central themes is Stein's answer
to the problem of the "romantic" Lord Jim in Conrad: "in the
destructive element immerse." This remark, without ridiculing Jim, still
brings out the quixotic and romantic element in his nature and criticizes it
from the point of view of experience. The chapter on watches and chronometers
in Melville's Pierre takes a similar attitude.
The fifth phase, corresponding to fatalistic or fifth-phase tragedy, is
irony in which the main emphasis is on the natural cycle, the steady unbroken
turning of the wheel of fate or fortune. It sees experience, in our terms, with
the point of epiphany closed up, and its motto is Browning's "there may be
heaven; there must be hell." Like the corresponding phase of tragedy, it
is less moral and more generalized and metaphysical in its interest, less
melioristic and more stoical and resigned. The treatment of Napoleon in War
and Peace and in The Dynastsaffords a good contrast
between the fourth and fifth phases of irony. The refrain in the Old
English Complaint of Deor: "Thaes ofereode; thisses swa
maeg" (freely [237] translatable as "Other people got through things;
maybe I can") expresses a stoicism not of the "invictus" type,
which maintains a romantic dignity, but rather a sense, found also in the
parallel second phase of satire, that the practical and immediate situation is
likely to be worthy of more respect than the theoretical explanation of it.
The sixth phase presents human life in terms of largely unrelieved
bondage. Its settings feature prisons, madhouses, lynching mobs, and places of
execution, and it differs from a pure inferno mainly in the fact that in human
experience suffering has an end in death. In our day the chief form of this
phase is the nightmare of social tyranny, of which 1984 is perhaps the most
familiar. We often find, on this boundary of the visio malefica,
the use of parody-religious symbols suggesting some form of Satan or Antichrist
worship. In Kafka's In the Penal Colony a parody of original
sin appears in the officer's remark, "Guilt is never to be doubted."
In 1984 the parody of religion in the final scenes is more elaborate: there is
a parody of the atonement, for instance, when the hero is tortured into urging
that the torments be inflicted on the heroine instead. The assumption is made
in this story that the lust for sadistic power on the part of the ruling class
is strong enough to last indefinitely, which is precisely the assumption one
has to make about devils in order to accept the orthodox picture of hell. The
"telescreen" device brings into irony the tragic theme of derkou
theama, the humiliation of being constantly watched by a hostile or
derisive eye.
The human figures of this phase are, of course, desdichado figures
of misery or madness, often parodies of romantic roles. Thus the romantic theme
of the helpful servant giant is parodied in The Hairy Ape and Of
Mice and Men, and the romantic presenter or Prospero figure is parodied in
the Benjy of The Sound and the Fury whose idiot mind contains,
without comprehending, the whole action of the novel. Sinister parental figures
naturally abound, for this is the world of the ogre and the witch, of
Baudelaire's black giantess and Pope's goddess Dullness, who also has much of
the parody deity about her ("Light dies before thy uncreating
word!"), of the siren with the imprisoning image of shrouding hair, and,
of course, of the femme fatale or malignant grinning female,
"older than the rocks among which she sits," as Pater says of her.
This brings us around again to the point of demonic epiphany, [238] the
dark tower and prison of endless pain, the city of dreadful night in the
desert, or, with a more erudite irony, the tour abolie, the goal of
the quest that isn't there. But on the other side of this blasted world of
repulsiveness and idiocy, a world without pity and without hope, satire begins
again. At the bottom of Dante's hell, which is also the center of the spherical
earth, Dante sees Satan standing upright in the circle of ice, and as he
cautiously follows Virgil over the hip and thigh of the evil giant, letting
himself down by the tufts of hair on his skin, he passes the center and finds
him self no longer going down but going up, climbing out on the other side of
the world to see the stars again. From this point of view, the devil is no
longer upright, but standing on his head, in the same attitude in which he was
hurled downward from heaven upon the other side of the earth. Tragedy and
tragic irony take us into a hell of narrowing circles and culminate in some
such vision of the source of all evil in a personal form. Tragedy can take us
no farther; but if we persevere with the mythos of irony and satire, we shall
pass a dead center, and finally see the gentlemanly Prince of Darkness bottom
side up. [239]
No comments:
Post a Comment